CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS

C. F. CLAY, MANAGER LONDON : FETTER LANE, E.C. 4

LONDON : H. K. LEWIS AND CO., LTD.,

136 Gower Street, W.C. i NEW YORK : THE MACMILLAN CO.

BOMBAY ^|

CALCUTTA [- MACMILLAN AND CO., LTD.

MADRAS J

TORONTO : THE MACMILLAN CO. OF

CANADA, LTD. TOKYO :MARUZEN-KABUSHIKI-KAISHA

ALL RIGHTS RESERVED

The

Principle of Relativity

with applications to

Physical Science

The

Principle of Relativity

with applications to Physical Science

BY A^ N. WHITEHEAD, Sc.D., F.R.S.

Hon. D.Sc. (MANCHESTER), Hon. LL.D. (Sx ANDREWS)

Fellow of Trinity College, Cambridge, and Professor of

Applied Mathematics in the Imperial College

of Science and Technology

M

CAMBRIDGE

AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS 1922

TO MY WIFE

WHOSE ENCOURAGEMENT AND COUNSEL HAVE MADE MY LIFE'S WORK POSSIBLE

PRINTED IN GREAT BRITAIN

PREFACE

THE present work is an exposition of an alternative rendering of the theory of relativity. It takes its rise from that ' awakening from dogmatic slumber' to use Kant's phrase which we owe to Einstein and Minkowski. But it is not an attempt to expound either Einstein's earlier or his later theory. The metrical for mulae finally arrived at are those of the earlier theory, but the meanings ascribed to the algebraic symbols are entirely different. As the result of a consideration of the character of our knowledge in general, and of our knowledge of nature in particular, undertaken in Part I of this book and in my two previous works* on this subject, I deduce that our experience requires and exhibits a basis of uniformity, and that in the case of nature this basis exhibits itself as the uniformity of spatio-temporal relations. This conclusion entirely cuts away the casual heterogeneity of these relations which is the essential of Einstein's later theory. It is this uniformity which is essential to my outlook, and not the Euclidean geometry which I adopt as lending itself to the simplest exposition of the facts of nature. I should be very willing to believe that each permanent space is either uniformly elliptic or uniformly hyperbolic, if any observations are more simply explained by such a hypothesis.

It is inherent in my theory to maintain the old division between physics and geometry. Physics is the

* The Principles of Natural Knowledge^ and The Concept of 'Nature, both Cambridge Univ. Press.

a3

vi PREFACE

science of the contingent relations of nature and geo metry expresses its uniform relatedness.

The book is divided into three parts. Part I is con cerned with general principles and may roughly be described as mainly philosophical in character. Part II is devoted to the physical applications and deals with the particular results deducible from the formulae assumed for the gravitational and electromagnetic fields. In relation to the spectral lines these formulae would require a 'limb effect' and a duplication or a triplication of indi vidual lines, analogous to phenomena already observed. Part III is an exposition of the elementary theory of tensors. This Part has been added for one reason because it may be useful to many mathematicians who may be puzzled by some of the formulae and procedures of Part II. But this Part is also required by another reason. The theory of tensors is usually expounded under the guise of geometrical metaphors which entirely mask the type of application which I give to it in this work. For example, the whole idea of any 'fundamental tensor' is foreign to my purpose and impedes the comprehension of my applications.

The order in which the parts should be studied will depend upon the psychology of the reader. I have placed them in the order natural to my own mind, namely, general principles, particular applications, and finally the general exposition of the mathematical theory of which special examples have occurred in the discussion of the applications. But a physicist may prefer to start with Part II, referring back to a few formulae which have been mentioned at the end of Part I, and a mathematician may start with Part III. The whole evidence requires a consideration of the three Parts.

PREFACE vii

Practically the whole of the book has been delivered in the form of lectures either in America at the College of Bryn Mawr, or before the Royal Society of Edinburgh, or to my pupils in the Imperial College. I have care fully preserved the lecture form and also some redupli cation of statement, particularly in Part I.

The exposition of a novel idea which has many reactions upon diverse current modes of thought is a difficult business. The most successful example in the history of science is, I think, Galileo's 'Dialogues on the Two Systems of the World.' An examination of that masterly work will show that the dialogue form is an essential element to its excellence. It allows the main expositor of the dialogues continually to restate his ideas in reference to diverse trains of thought suggested by the other interlocutors. Now the process of understanding new conceptions is essentially the process of laying the new ideas alongside of our pre-existing trains of thought. Accordingly for an author of adequate literary ability the dialogue is the natural literary form for the pro longed explanation of a tangled subject. The custom of modern presentations of science, and my own diffi dence of success in the art of managing a dialogue, have led me to adopt the modified form of lectures in which the audiences real audiences, either in America, Edinburgh or South Kensington are to be regarded as silent interlocutors demanding explanations of the various aspects of the theory.

Chapter II was originally delivered* in Edinburgh

as a lecture to the Royal Society of Edinburgh when

it did me the honour of making me the first recipient of

the 'James-Scott Prize' for the encouragement of the

* June 5, 1922.

viii PREFACE

philosophy of science. Chapter IV was originally delivered* at the College of Bryn Mawr, near Phila delphia, on the occasion of a festival promoted by the former pupils and colleagues of Prof. Charlotte Angus Scott in honour of her work as Professor of Mathematics at the college since its foundation.

My thanks are due to my colleague, Assistant-Pro fessor Sillick, for the figure on p. 31. I am also further indebted to him for a series of beautiful slides containing the mathematical formulae of Chapter IV; even the admirable printing of the Cambridge University Press will not compensate readers of this book for the loss of the slides as used in the original lecture.

In acknowledging my obligations to the efficiency and courtesy of the staff of the University Press, I take the opportunity of paying a respectful tribute to the work of the late Mr A. H. Waller as secretary of the Press Syndicate. The initial negotiations respecting this book were conducted through him and he died just as the printing commenced. The loss of his wisdom, his knowledge, and his charm will leave a gap in the hearts of all those who have to deal with the great Institution which he served so well.

* April 18, 1922.

A. N. W.

15 September, 1922.

TABLE OF CONTENTS PART I. GENERAL PRINCIPLES

PAGES

CHAPTER I. PREFATORY EXPLANATIONS 3-12

Scope of doctrine of relativity : the two gauges : philosophy : Poyn ting's aphorism : time and space : physical objects : the planet Mercury: spectral lines, shift, limb effect and duplication: two novel magnetic forces in steady fields : temperature effect.

II. THE RELATEDNESS OF NATURE . . . 13-39

1 James-Scott Prize ' : Hume and relatedness : a ground of uni formity : fact and factors : awareness, cogitation and entities : fact not an entity : concreteness, embeddedness, factuality : limitation, fmitude, canalisation : examples : the significance of factors : active and passive cognisance, cognisance by adjective and cognisance by relatedness : full awareness : spatio-temporal relationships : sense- awareness and nature : nature significant of ideality : nature, time and space, events : nature as a closed system : objection to doctrine of relatedness, truth incompatible with any i^imrancc: essential and contingent relationships : significance concerned with essential rela tionships : every factor uniformly significant : patience of fact for each factor : examples : uniform significance of events, spatio-temporal structure: dissent from Einstein: stratification, patience of fact for finite consciousness: objects and recognition: a field: two-termed relation between universals and concrete particulars : observer's mind : solipsism : adjectives of events : contraction of sphere of contingency : structure of the continuum of events : past, present, future, causal past, causal future, co-present region : spatial routes, historical routes : per vasive adjectives and adjectival particles: individuality and process: pseudo-adjectives and sense-objects : atomic field of an adjectival particle : scientific objects qualify future events : permanence and field : critical velocity c : velocity of light : tubes of force : obstructed fields : ether and the apparent world identical: ether of events: events sup plant stuff: Descartes on space and time : necessity of definite meaning for symbols.

III. EQUALITY 40-60

Importance of equality: equality, congruence, quantity, measure ment, identity, diversity: Euclid's axiom: «ros: characteristics of the equality relation: matching: congruence of stretches: axiom of Archimedes: Sophus Lie: multiplicity of inconsistent congruence relations : gap in classical theory : necessity of structure : straight lines, planes, order, parallelism, rectangularity : space, bodies, events : origin of parallelism: origin of perpendicularity: impossibility of deriving time from permanent bodies : Einstein and alternative time- systems : order in space derivative from order in time.

x TABLE OF CONTENTS

<*'

PAGES

IV. SOME PRINCIPLES OF PHYSICAL SCIENCE 41-88 The apparent world : bifurcation of nature: two-fold cognisance, cognisance by adjective, cognisance by relatedness : systematic coherency of nature : events and two-fold cognisance : perception : the contingency of appearance : the uniform significance of events : the yard-measure: doctrine of time: time a stratification of nature: no unique system of temporal stratification : Einstoin : simultaneity fundamental : appearance is nature : time and space, their assimila tion and distinction : spatial and historical routes : individuality of adjectival particles derivative from their historical routes: time- systems and parallelism: Euclidean assumption, slight evidence: permanent space of a time-system derivative from rest and motion : permanent points : spatial and temporal relations of permanent bodies arise mediately : the physical field : limitation of the contingency of appearance: intermediate distribution of character attachable to future events : physical field not cause of perception : physical field atomic: physical atomic character exemplifies Aristotelian attribute: knowledge impossible without atomicity: systematic relatedness, intelligibility due to uniformity and to atomicity of the contingent: sense in which physical field is perceived: adjectival particles: their definition: pervasion: they involve stretches of route: kinematic elements: mass-particles: kinematic past, kinematic future, region co-present, causal past, causal future: Faraday's tubes of force: metrical formulae : impetus : potential mass impetus, potential electro magnetic impetus: realised impetus: stationary property of realised impetus: gravitational field: an integral law of gravitation: com parison with Einstein's law: conditions fulfilled: four alternative laws satisfying all conditions at present known : rotation : the genius of Einstein and Minkowski.

PART II. PHYSICAL APPLICATIONS

V. THE EQUATIONS OF MOTION .... 91-92 Derivative forms of the equations: the pure centrifugal gravitational

terms : the composite centrifugal gravitational terms : the pure gravitational term.

VI. ON THE FORMULA FOR dJ* .... 93-100 Fundamental formulae : the general potential : the tensor potential :

the first associate potential: the second associate potential: the contemporary positions : the associated space.

VII. PERMANENT GRAVITATIONAL FIELDS 101

VIII. APPARENT MASS AND THE SPECTRAL SHIFT . . ... 102-103

IX. PLANETARY MOTION . 104-105

TABLE OF CONTENTS xi

PAGES

X. ELECTROMAGNETIC EQUATIONS . . 106-107

XI. GRAVITATION AND LIGHT WAVES . 108-111

XII. TEMPERATURE EFFECTS ON GRAVITA TIONAL FORCES 112-113

XIII. THE ELECTROSTATIC POTENTIAL AND SPECTRAL SHIFT 114-116

XIV. THE LIMB EFFECT 117-120

XV. PERMANENT DIRECTIONS OF VIBRA TION AND THE DOUBLING EFFECT . 121-126

XVI. STEADY ELECTROMAGNETIC FIELDS . 127-131

XVII. THE MOON'S MOTION ... . . 132-136

PART III. ELEMENTARY THEORY OF TENSORS

XVIII. FUNDAMENTAL NOTIONS . . . 139-147 SECTION 1. Coordinates: 2. Scalar Characters and Invariant Ex pressions: 3. Physical Characters of the First Order: 4. Tensors of the First Order: 5. Covariant and Contra variant First-Order Tensors : 6. Characters and Tensors of Higher Orders : 7. Tensor- Invariance of Formulae.

XIX. ELEMENTARY PROPERTIES . . . 148-152 SECTIONS. Test for Tensor Property : 9. Sum of Tensors : 10. Pro duct of Tensors : 11. Representation of a Tensor as a Sum of Products.

XX. THE PROCESS OF RESTRICTION . . . 153-159 SECTION 12. Definition of Restriction : 13. Multiple Restriction :

14. Invariant Products: 15. The Tensor ||/||: 16. Restriction of a Single Mixed Tensor: 17. Argument from Products [Restricted or Unrestricted] to the Tensor Property: 18. Differential Forms.

XXL TENSORS OF THE SECOND ORDER . . 160-165 SECTION 19. Symmetric Tensors : 20. Skew Tensors: 21. The Determinants: 22. Associate Tensors: 23. Derivative Tensors.

XXII. THE GALILEAN TENSOR .... 166-172

SECTION 24. Galilean Tensors : 25. Galilean Differential Forms :

26. The Linear Equations of Transformation : 27. Cartesian Group :

28. Associate Galilean Tensors and Galilean Derivative Tensors :

29. Galilean Derivative Tensors of the First Order.

xii TABLE OF CONTENTS

PAGES

XXIII. THE DIFFERENTIATION OF TENSOR COMPONENTS 173-183

SECTION 30. The Christoffel Three-Index Symbols: 31. Differentia tion of Determinants of Tensors : 32. The Standard Formulae : 33. Covariant Tensors of the First Order : 34. Contravariant Tensors of the First Order: 35. An Example: 36. Tensors of the Second Order: 37. Tensors of the Third Order.

XXIV. SOME IMPORTANT TENSORS . . . 184-190 SECTION 38. The Riemann-Christoffel Tensor: 39. The Linear

Gravitational Tensor : 40. Cyclic Reduction : 41. Some Cartesian Group-Tensors.

PART I

GENERAL PRINCIPLES

W. R.

CHAPTER I

PREFATORY EXPLANATIONS

THE doctrine of relativity affects every branch of natural science, not excluding the biological sciences. In general, however, this impact of the new doctrine on the older sciences lies in the future and will disclose itself in ways not yet apparent. Relativity, in the form of novel formulae relating time and space, first developed in con nection with electromagnetism, including light pheno mena. Einstein then proceeded to show its bearing on the formulae for gravitation. It so happens therefore that owing to the circumstances of its origin a very general doctrine is linked with two special applications.

In this procedure science is evolving according to its usual mode. In that atmosphere of thought doctrines are valued for their utility as instruments of research. Only one question is asked : Has the doctrine a precise application to a variety of particular circumstances so as to determine the exact phenomena which should be then observed? In the comparative absence of these applications beauty, generality, or even truth, will not save a doctrine from neglect in scientific thought. With them, it will be absorbed.

Accordingly a new scientific outlook clings to those fields where its first applications are to be found. They are its title deeds for consideration. But in testing its truth, if the theory have the width and depth which marks a fundamental reorganisation, we cannot wisely confine ourselves solely to the consideration of a few happy applications. The history of science is strewn with the happy applications of discarded theories. There

1—2

4 PREFATORY EXPLANATIONS [OH

are two gauges through which every theory must pass. There is the broad gauge which tests its consonance with the general character of our direct experience, and there is the narrow gauge which is that mentioned above as being the habitual working gauge of science. These reflections have been suggested by the advice received from two distinguished persons to whom at different times I had explained the scheme of this book. The philosopher advised me to omit the mathematics, and the mathematician urged the cutting out of the philo sophy. At the moment I was persuaded: it certainly is a nuisance for philosophers to be worried with applied mathematics, and for mathematicians to be saddled with philosophy. But further reflection has made me retain my original plan. The difficulty is inherent in the subject matter.

To expect to reorganise our ideas of Time, Space, and Measurement without some discussion which must be ranked as philosophical is to neglect the teaching of history and the inherent probabilities of the subject. On the other hand no reorganisation of these ideas can command confidence unless it supplies science with added power in the analysis of phenomena. The evidence is twro-fold, and is fatally weakened if the two parts are disjoined.

At the same time it is well to understand the limita-^1 tions to the meaning of 'philosophy' in this connection. It has nothing to do with ethics or theology or the theory of aesthetics. It is solely engaged in determining the most general conceptions which apply to things observed by the senses. Accordingly it is not even metaphysics : it should be called pan-physics. Its task is to formulate those principles of science which are

i] PREFATORY EXPLANATIONS 5

employed equally in every branch of natural science. | Sir J. J. Thomson, reviewing in Nature* Poynting's Collected Papers, has quoted a statement taken from rone of Poynting's addresses :

' I have no doubt whatever that our ultimate aim must be to describe the sensible in terms of the sensible.'

Adherence to this aphorism, sanctioned by the authority of two great English physicists, is the keynote of everything in the following chapters. The philosophy J of science is the endeavour to formulate the most general I characters of things observed. These sought-for charac ters are to be no fancy characters of a fairy tale enacted behind the scenes. They must be observed characters! of things observed. Nature is what is observed, and the ether is an observed character of things observed. Thus the philosophy of science only differs from any of the special natural sciences by the fact that it is natural science at the stage before it is convenient to split it up into its various branches. This philosophy exists because there is something to be said before we commence the process of differentiation. It is true that in human thought the particular precedes the general. Accord ingly the philosophy will not advance until the branches of science have made independent progress. Philosophy then appears as a criticism and a corrective, and what is now to the purpose as an additional source of evi dence in times of fundamental reorganisation.

This assignment of the role of philosophy is borne out by history. It is not true that science has advanced in disregard of any general discussion of the character of the universe. The scientists of the Renaissance and their immediate successors of the seventeenth century, * Dec. 30, 1920.

PREFATORY EXPLANATIONS

[CH

to whom we owe our traditional concepts, inherited from Plato, Aristotle and the medieval scholastics. It is true that the New Learning reacted violently against the schoolmen who were their immediate predecessors; but, like the Israelites when they fled from Egypt, they borrowed their valuables and in this case the valuables were certain root-presuppositions respecting space, time, matter, predicate and subject, and logic in general. It is legitimate (as a practical counsel in the management of a short life) to abstain from the criticism of scientific foundations so long as the superstructure ' works. ' But to neglect philosophy when engaged in the re-formation of ideas is to assume the absolute correctness of the chance philosophic prejudices imbibed from a nurse or a schoolmaster or current modes of expression. It is to enact the part of those who thank Providence that they have been saved from the perplexities of religious en quiry by the happiness of birth in the true faith. The truth is that your available concepts depend upon your philosophy. An examination of the writings of John Stuart Mill and his immediate successors on the pro cedure of science writings of the highest excellence within their limitations will show that they are ex clusively considering the procedure of science in the framing of laws with the employment of given concepts. If this limitation be admitted, the conclusion at once follows that philosophy is useless in the progress of science. But when once you tamper with your basic concepts, philosophy is merely the marshalling of one main source of evidence, and cannot be neglected.

But when all has been said respecting the importance , of philosophy for the discovery of scientific truth, the I narrow-gauged pragmatic test will remain the final

i] PREFATORY EXPLANATIONS 7

arbiter. Accordingly I now proceed to a summary account of the general doctrine either implicit or explicit in the following pages or in my two previous books * on this subject, and to detail the facts of experience which receive their explanation from it or should be observed if it be true.

A relativistic view of time is adopted so that an in stantaneous moment of time is nothing else than an instantaneous and simultaneous spread of the events of the universe. But in the concept of instantaneousness the concept of the passage of time has been lost. Events essentially involve this passage. Accordingly the self- contradictory idea of an instantaneous event has to be replaced by that of an instantaneous configuration of the universe. But what is directly observed is an event. Thus a duration, which is a slab of time with temporal thickness, is the final fact of observation from which moments and configurations are deduced as a limit which is a logical ideal of the exact precision inherent in nature. This process of deducing limits is considered in detail in my two previous books under the title Extensive Abstraction. But it is an essential assump tion that a concrete fact of nature always includes temporal passage.

A moment expresses the spread of nature as a con figuration in an instantaneous three dimensional space. The flow of time means the succession of moments, and this succession includes the whole of nature. Rest and motion are direct facts of observation concerning the relation of objects to the durations whose limits are the moments of this flow of time. By means of rest a

* The Principles of Natural Knowledge, and The Concept of Nature, both Camb. Univ. Press.

8 PREFATORY EXPLANATIONS [en

permanent point is defined which is merely a track of event-particles with one event-particle in every moment.

Refined observation (in the form of the Michelson- Morley experiment and allied experiments) shows that there are alternative flows of time or time-systems, as they will be called, and that the time-system actually observed is that one for which (roughly speaking) our body is at rest. Accordingly in different circumstances of motion, space and time mean different things, the moments of one time-system are different from the moments of another time-system, the per manent points of one time-system are different from those of another time-system, so that the permanent space of one time-system is distinct from the permanent space of another time-system.

The properties of time and space express the basis of uniformity in nature which is essential for our know ledge of nature as a coherent system. The physical field expresses the unessential uniformities regulating the contingency of appearance. In a fuller consideration of experience they may exhibit themselves as essential; but if we limit ourselves to nature there is no essential reason for the particular nexus of appearance.

Thus times and spaces are uniform.

Position in space is merely the expression of diversity of relations to alternative time -systems. Order in space is merely the reflection into the space of one time-system of the time-orders of alternative time-systems.

A plane in space expresses the quality of the locus of intersection of a moment of the time-system in question (call it 'time-system A ') with a moment of another time- system (time-system B).

The parallelism of planes in the space of time-system A means that these planes result from the intersections

i] PREFATORY EXPLANATIONS 9

of moments of A with moments of one other time- system B.

A straight line in the space of time-system A perpen dicular to the planes due to time-system B is the track in the space of time-system A of a body at rest in the space of time-system B.

Thus the uniform Euclidean geometry of spaces, planeness, parallelism, and perpendicularity are merely expressive of the relations to each other of alternative time-systems.

The tracks which are the permanent points of the same time -system are also reckoned as parallels.

Congruence and thence, spatial measurement is defined in terms of the properties of parallelograms and the symmetry of perpendicularity.

Accordingly, position, planes, straight lines, paral lelism, perpendicularity, and congruence are expressive of the mutual relations of alternative time-systems.

The symmetrical properties of relative velocity are shown (in The Principles of Natural Knowledge] to issue in a critical velocity c, which thus is defined with out reference to the velocity of light. However experi ment shows that for our purposes it must be a near approach to that velocity. The final result is the geo metry and kinematic which are explained in Chapter iv of the present volume.

A physical object, such as a mass-particle or an elec tron, expresses the character of the future so far as it is determined by the happenings of the present. The exact meaning of an object as an entity implicated in events is explained. The track of an object amid events is determined by the ' stationary ' property of the impetus realised by the pervasion of the track by the object. This impetus depends partly on the intrinsic character

10 PBEFATORY EXPLANATIONS [OH

of the object e.g. its mass or its electric charge and partly on the intrinsic potential impetus of the track itself. This potential impetus arises from the physical character of the events of the region due to the presence of other objects in the past. This physical character is partly gravitational and partly electrical.

This dependence of physical character on antecedent objects is directly expressed by the formula here adopted for the gravitational law. This law also gives the most direct expression to the principle that the flux of time is essential to the concrete reality of nature, so that a loss of time-flux means a transference to a higher ab straction. It gives this expression by conceiving the attracting body as pervading an element of its track and not as at an event-particle. This law gives the Einstein expression for the revolution of the perihelion of Mercury.

The electromagnetic equations adopted are Maxwell's equations modified by the gravitational tensor compo nents in the well-known way. Light is given no privi leged position, and all deductions concerning light follow directly from treating it as consisting of short waves of electromagnetic disturbance. In this way Einstein's assumption that a ray of light follows the path

[i.e. in Einstein's notation

ds2 = 0]

can be proved as an approximation due to the shortness of the waves.

The bending of the light rays in a gravitational field then follows.

With regard to the shift of spectral lines, there are

i] PREFATORY EXPLANATIONS 11

three effects to be considered: (i) Einstein's predicted shift due to the gravitational potential, (ii) the limb effect which has been observed in the case of light from the sun, (iii) the doubling or trebling of spectral lines observed in the spectra due to some nebulae. Neither of the effects (ii) or (iii) has hitherto been explained.

As to (i) this is traced to the combination of two causes, one being the change in the apparent mass due to the gravitational potential and the other being the change in the electric cohesive forces of the molecule due to the gravitational field. The total result is that the period of vibration is changed from T to T+ST7, where

T 6c2'

i//4 being the gravitational potential. Einstein's result is t/>4/c% so that the two formulae are practically identical for observational purposes.

With regard to effects (ii) and (iii) reasons are given for believing that the molecules will separate into three groups sending a distant observer light of changing relative intensities as we pass from the centre of the disc of the emitting body (sun or nebulae) to the edge. One group has the above-mentioned shift, another has the shift

~

(where 77 is probably about 1/10, but may be nearly 1/5), and the third group has the shift

8T_2+2

T *'"WVi-

Under circumstances such that all or two of the groups send separately observable light, the trebling or doubling effects are explained to the extent of demonstrating the

12 PREFATORY EXPLANATIONS [OH i

existence of causes for the multiplication of lines, other than those due to the motions of the matter of the nebulae. Under other circumstances (e.g. light from the sun's disc) in which the influence of the grouping is effective but not separately observable the shift approximates to ^ T 1

j + l -

where ySx varies from zero at the centre of the disc of the sun to ?r/2 at its edge. But there will be various intermediate circumstances between these extreme as sumptions as to the observability of the grouping effect.

Finally in a steady electromagnetic field the electro magnetic equations predict two novel magnetic forces due to the gravitational field. These forces are exces sively small: (i) A steady electric force at a point on the earth's surface (F in electrostatic units) should be accompanied by the horizontal magnetic force

r2xlO~9x.Fsma (gausses)

perpendicular to its direction and to the vertical, where a is the angle between these directions.

(ii) A steady current (/ in electromagnetic measure) in a straight wire making an angle /3 with the vertical should produce at a point distant R from the wire the parallel magnetic force (i.e. in a direction parallel to the wire),

1 27

- x 10~9x cos sin 2/3 x -^ (gausses),

where is the angle between the vertical plane through the wire and the plane through the wire and the point. The temperature of an attracting body should augment its gravitational field by an amount which is probably outside the limits of our observational powers.

CHAPTER II

THE RELATEDNESS OF NATURE

"Threads and floating wisps Of being, ..."

CLEMENCE DANE'S Will Shakespeare, Act i.

You have conferred upon me the honour of becoming the first recipient of the 'James-Scott Prize,' and have at the same time assigned to me the duty of delivering a lecture upon the subject which this prize is designed to foster. In choosing the topic of a lecture which is to be the first of a series upon the philosophy of science, it seems suitable to explore the broadest possible aspect of the subject. Accordingly I propose to address you upon Relatedness and, in particular, upon the Related- ness of Nature. I feel some natural diffidence in speaking upon this theme in the capital of British metaphysics, haunted by the shade of Hume. This great thinker made short work of the theory of the relatedness of nature as it existed in the current philosophy of his time. It is hardly too much to say that the course of subsequent philosophy, including even Hume's own later writings and the British Empirical School, but still more in the stream which descends through Kant, Hegel and Caird, has been an endeavour to restore some theory of relatedness to replace the one demolished by Hume's youthful scepticism. If you once conceive fundamental fact as a multiplicity of subjects qualified by predicates, you must fail to give a coherent account of experience. The disjunction of subjects is the pre supposition from which you start, and you can only

14 THE RELATEDNESS OF NATURE [OH

account for conjunctive relations by some fallacious sleight of hand, such as Leibniz's metaphor of his monads engaged in mirroring. The alternative philosophic posi tion must commence with denouncing the whole idea of ' subject qualified by predicate ' as a trap set for philosophers by the syntax of language. The conclusion which I shall wish to enforce is that we can discern in nature a ground of uniformity, of which the more far- reaching example is the uniformity of space-time and the more limited example is what is usually known under the title, The Uniformity of Nature. My argu ments must be based upon considerations of the utmost generality untouched by the peculiar features of any particular natural science. It is therefore inevitable that at the beginning my exposition will suffer from the vagueness which clings to generality.

Fact is a relationship of factors. Every factor of fact essentially refers to its relationships within fact. Apart from this reference it is not itself. Thus every factor of fact has fact for its background, and refers to fact in a way peculiar to itself.

I shall use the term ' awareness ' for consciousness of factors within fact. A converse mode of statement is that awareness is consciousness of fact as involving factors. Awareness is itself a factor within fact.

I shall use the term ' cogitation' for consciousness of factors prescinded from their background of fact. It is the consciousness of the individuality of factors, in that each factor is itself and not another. A factor cogitated upon as individual will be called an 'entity.' The essence of cogitation is consciousness of diversity. The prescinding from the background of fact consists in limiting consciousness to awareness of the contrast of

ii] THE RELATEDNESS OF NATURE 15

factors. Cogitation thus presupposes awareness and is limited by the limitations of awareness. It is the re finement of awareness, and the unity of consciousness lies in this dependence of cogitation upon awareness. Thus awareness is crude consciousness and cogitation is refined consciousness. For awareness all relations between factors are internal and for cogitation all relations between entities are external.

Fact in its totality is not an entity for cogitation, since it has no individuality by its reference to any thing other than itself. It is not a relatum in the relationship of contrast. I might have used the term ' totality ' instead of ' fact ' ; but c fact ' is shorter and gives rise to the convenient term * factor.' Fact enters consciousness in away peculiar to itself. It is not the sum of factors ; it is rather the concreteness (or, embedded- ness) of factors, and the concreteness of an inexhaustible relatedness among inexhaustible relata. If for one moment I may use the inadmissible word 'Factuality,' it is in some ways better either than 'fact' or 'totality' for the expression of my meaning. For 'fact' suggests one fact among others. This is not what I mean, and is a sub ordinate meaning which I express by 'factor.' Also 'totality' suggests a definite aggregate which is all that there is, and which can be constructed as the sum of all subordinate aggregates. I deny this view of factuality. For example, in the very conception of the addition of subordinate aggregates, the concept of the addition is omitted although this concept is itself a factor of factuality. Thus inexhaustibleness is the prime character of factuality as disclosed in awareness ; that is to say, factuality (even as in individual awareness) cannot be exhausted by any definite class of factors.

16 THE KELATEDNESS OF NATURE [CH

After this explanation I will now relapse into the use of ' fact ' in the sense of ' factuality.'

The finiteness of consciousness, the factorisation of fact, the individualisation of entities in cogitation, and the opposition of abstract to concrete are all exhibitions of the same truth of the existence of limitation within fact. The abstract is a limitation within the concrete, the entity is a limitation within totality, the factor is a limitation within fact, and consciousness by its reference to its own standpoint within fact limits fact to fact as apprehended in consciousness. The treatment of the whole theory of limitation has suffered by the introduc tion of metaphors derived from a highly particular form of it, namely, derived from the analogy between extended things, such as that of whole to part and that of things mutually external to each other.

I use the term * limitation ' for the most general conception of fmitude. In a somewhat more restricted sense Bergson uses the very convenient term ' canalisa tion.' This Bergsonian term is a useful one to keep in mind as a corrective to the misleading associations of the terms ' external ' and ' internal/ or of the terms 'whole' and 'part.' It adds also a content to the negative term 'limitation.' Thus a factor is a limitation of fact in the sense that a factor refers to fact canalised into a system of relata to itself, i.e. to the factor in question. The mere negative limitation, or finitude, in volved in a factor is exhibited in cogitation, wherein the factor degenerates into an entity and the canalisation degenerates into a bundle of external relations.

Thus also finite consciousness is a limitation of fact, in the sense that it is a factor canalising fact in ways peculiar to itself. We must get rid of the notion of

ii] THE RELATEDNESS OF NATURE 17

consciousness as a little box with some things inside it. A better metaphor is that of the contact of conscious ness with other factors, which is practically Hume's metaphor ' impression.' But this metaphor erroneously presupposes that fact as disclosed in awareness can be constructed as an entity formed by the sum of the impressions of isolated factors.

Again cogitation is a further limitation of fact in that it is a canalisation of consciousness so as to divest it of the crudeness of awareness. This illustrates that in limitation there is a gain in clarity, or definition, or intensity, but a loss of content.

For example, the factor red refers to fact as canalised by relationships of other factors to red, and the entity red is the factor red in its capacity as a relatum in the relationship of contrast, whereby it is contrasted with green or with sound or with the moon or with the multiplication table. Thus the factor red, essentially for its being, occasions the exhibition of a special aspect of fact, and the entity red is a further limitation of this aspect. Similarly the number three is nothing else than the aspect of fact as factors grouped in triplets. And the Tower of London is a particular aspect of the Universe in its relation to the banks of the Thames. Thus an entity is an abstraction from the concrete, which in its fullest sense means totality.

The point of this doctrine on which I want to insist is that any factor, by virtue of its status as a limitation within totality, necessarily refers to factors of totality other than itself. It is therefore impossible to find any thing finite, that is to say, any entity for cogitation, which does not in its apprehension by consciousness disclose relationships to other entities, and thereby dis- w. R. 2

18 THE RELATEDNESS OF NATURE [CH

close some systematic structure of factors within fact. I call this quality of finitude, the significance of factors. This doctrine of significance necessitates that we admit that awareness requires a dual cognisance of entities. There can be awareness of a factor as signifying, and awareness of a factor as signified. In a sense this may be represented as an active or a passive cognisance of the entity. The entity is either cognised for its own sake, that is to say, actively, or it is cognised for the sake of other entities, that is to say, passively. If an entity is cognised actively, it is cognised for the sake of what it is in itself, for the sake of what it can make of the universe. I will call this sort of awareness of a factor, cognisance by adjective; since it is the character of the factor in itself which is then dominant in conscious ness. Although in cognisance by adjective an entity is apprehended as a definite character in its relations to other entities, yet in a sense this type of cognisance marks a breakdown in relatedness. For the general relatedness of the character to other factors merely marks the fullness of its content, so that in effect the character is cognised for what it is in itself. Relation ships to other factors occur in such cognisance only because the character is not itself apart from that ordering of fact.

When an entity is cognised passively, we are aware of it for the sake of some other factor. We are conscious passively of factor A, because factor B of which we are actively aware would not be what it is apart from its relatedness to A. Thus the individual character of A is in the background, and A becomes a vague something which is an element in a complex of systematic related- ness. The very nature of the relatedness may impose

n] THE RELATEDNESS OF NATURE 19

on A some character. But the character is gained through the relatedness and not the relatedness through the character. Accordingly A gains in consciousness the very minimum foothold for the relationship of contrast, and is thus the most shadowy of entities. I will call this sort of awareness of a factor, cognisance by relatednoss. For example the knowledge of events inside another room is to be gained by their spatial and other relationships to events of which we have cognisance by adjective.

Thus cognisance of one factor by relatedness pre supposes cognisance of other factors by adjective; and conversely, cognisance of one factor by adjective pre supposes cognisance of other factors by relatedness.

It is possible to be aware of a factor both in cognisance by adjective and cognisance by relatedness. This will be termed ' full awareness ' of the factor and is the usual form of awareness of factors within the area of clear apprehension when intrinsic characters and mutual relations are jointly apparent. 'Perception' will be the name given to the consciousness of a factor when to full awareness cogitation of it as an entity is also superadded.

But cogitation does not necessarily presuppose full awareness. For the contrast involved in cogitation may simply fall on the quality of the individualities of the factors, as when green as such is contrasted with red as such. In such a case merely awareness by adjective is presupposed. But the contrast may also fall on the specific relationships of each of the two factors to other factors, as when we contrast an event in the interior of the moon with another event in the interior of the earth. The spatio-temporal relationships of the two

2—2

20 THE KELATEDNESS OF NATUKE [CH

events are then contrasted ; and it is from contrasts of this type that the two events gain their definite individuality as entities.

At this point in the discussion I will confine the scope of the remainder of my lecture strictly to the considera tion of the relatedness of nature. This requires us to recognise another limitation within awareness which cuts across those already mentioned. I mean the limita tion of awareness to sense-awareness. Nature is the system of factors apprehended in sense-awareness. But sense-awareness can only be defined negatively by enumerating what it is not.

Divest consciousness of its ideality, such as its logical, emotional, aesthetic and moral apprehensions, and what is left is sense-awareness. Thus sense-awareness is consciousness minus its apprehensions of ideality. It is not asserted that there is consciousness in fact divested of ideality, but that awareness of ideality and sense- awareness are two factors discernible in consciousness. The question as to whether either the one or the other, or both jointly may not be a factor necessary for consciousness is beyond the scope of the present dis cussion. The finiteness of individual consciousness means ignorance of what is there for knowledge. There is limitation of factors cognised by adjective, and equally there is limitation of factors cognised by relatedness. So it is perfectly possible to hold, as I do hold, that nature is significant of ideality, without being at all certain that there may not be some awareness of nature without awareness of ideality as signified by nature. It would have, I think, to be a feeble awareness. Per haps it is more likely that ideality and nature are dim together in dim consciousness. ~It is unnecessary for us to endeavour to solve these doubts. My essential premise

nj THE RELATEDNESS OF NATURE 21

is that we are conscious of a certain definite assemblage of factors within fact and that this assemblage is what I call nature. Also I entirely agree that the factors of nature are also significant of factors which are not included in nature. But I propose to ignore this admitted preternatural significance of nature, and to analyse the general character of the relatedness of natural entities between themselves.

Nature usually presents itself to our imagination as being composed of all those entities which are to be found somewhere at some time. Sabre-toothed tigers are part of nature because we believe that somewhere and at some time sabre-toothed tigers were prowling. Thus an essential significance of a factor of nature is its reference to something that happened in time and space. I give the name ' event ' to a spatio-temporal happening. An event does not in any way imply rapid change ; the endurance of a block of marble is an event. Nature presents itself to us as essentially a becoming, and any limited portion of nature which preserves most com pletely such concreteness as attaches to nature itself is also a becoming and is what I call an event. By this I do not mean a bare portion of space- time. Such a concept is a further abstraction. I mean a part of the becomingness of nature, coloured with all the hues of its content.

Thus nature is a becomingness of events which are mutually significant so as to form a systematic structure. We express the character of the systematic structure of events in terms of space and time. Thus space and time are abstractions from this structure.

Let us now examine more particularly the significance of events in so far as it falls within nature. In this way we are treating nature as a closed system, and this I

22 THE EELATEDNESS OF NATURE [OH

believe is the standpoint of natural science in the strict sense of the term.

But before embarking on the details of this investiga tion I should like to draw your attention to an objection, and a very serious objection, which is urged by opponents of the whole philosophic standpoint which I have been developing. You admit, it is said, that a factor is not itself apart from its relations to other factors. Ac cordingly to express any truth about one entity you must take into account its relations to all entities. But this is beyond you. Hence, since unfortunately a pro position must be either right or wrong or else unmeaning and a mere verbal jangle, the attainment of truth in any finite form is also beyond you.

Now I do not think that it is any answer to this argument to say that our propositions are only a little wrong, any more than it is a consolation to his friends to say that a man is only a little dead. The gist of the argument is that on our theory any ignorance is blank ignorance, because knowledge of any factor requires no ignorance. A philosophy of relatedness which cannot answer this argument must collapse, since we have got to admit ignorance.

Obviously if this argument is to be answered, I must guard and qualify some of the statements which have been made in the earlier portion of this lecture. I have put off the job until now, partly for the sake of simplicity, not to say too much at once, and also partly because the line of argument is most clearly illustrated in the case of nature, and indeed the application to nature is the only one in which for the purposes of this lecture we are interested. So I have waited until my discourse had led me to the introduction of nature.

ii] THE KELATEDNESS OF NATURE 23

The answer can only take one road, we must dis tinguish between the essential and the contingent relationships of a factor. The essential relationships of a factor are those relationships which are inherent in the peculiar individuality of the factor, so that apart from them the factor is not the special exhibition of finitude within fact which it is. They are the relation ships which place the factor as an entity amid a definite system of entities. The significance of a factor is solely concerned with its essential relationships. The con tingent relationships of a factor are those relationships between that factor and other factors which might be otherwise without change of the particular individuality of the factor. In other words, the factor would be what it is even if its contingent relationships were otherwise.

Thus awareness of a factor must include awareness of its essential relationships, and is compatible with ignorance of its contingent relationships.

It is evident that essential and contingent relationships correspond closely to internal and external relations. I hesitate to say how closely, since a different philosophic outlook radically affects all meanings.

We still have to explain how awareness of a factor can exclude ignorance of the relationships involved in its significance. For, on the face of it, this doctrine means that to perceive factor A we require also to per ceive factors B, C, D, etc., which A signifies. In view of the possibilities of ignorance, such a doctrine appears to be extremely doubtful. This objection ignores the analysis of awareness into cognisance by adjective and cognisance by relatedness. In order to perceive A we do not require to be conscious of B, (7, D, with cognisance by adjective. We only require cognisance by relatedness.

24 THE RELATEDNESS OF NATURE [CH

In other words we must be conscious of B, C, D, ... as

entities requisite for that relatedness to A, which is in volved in A's significance. But even this explanation asks for too much. It suggests that we must be conscious of B, C, D, ... as a definite numerical aggregate of entities signified by A. Now it is evident that no factor A makes us conscious of the individual entities of such an aggregate. Some necessary qualification of the doc trine of significance has been omitted. The missing principle is that any factor A has to be uniformly significant. [Every entity involves that fact shall be patient of it.JJThe patience of fact for A is the converse side of the significance of A within fact.j This involves a canalisation within fact ; and this means a systematic aggregate of factors each with the uniform impress of the patience of fact for A. A can be, because they are. Each such factor individually expresses the patience of fact for A.

Thus the knowledge required by the significance of A is simply this. In order to know A wejnust ^now how other factors express the patience of fact for A^ We need not be aware of these other factors individually, but the awareness of A does require an awareness of their defining character. There is no such entity as mere A in isolation. A requires something other than itself, namely, factors expressing the patience of fact in respect to factor A.

Let us now apply to nature this doctrine of uniform significance. We commence by taking the case of the colour green. When we perceive green, it is not green in isolation, it is green somewhere at some time. The green may or may not have the relationship to some other object, such as a blade of grass. Such a relation

n] THE RELATEDNESS OF NATURE 25

would be contingent. But it is essential that we see it somewhere in space related to our eyes at a certain epoch of our bodily life. The detailed relationships of green to our bodily life and to the situations in which it is apparent to our vision are complex and variable and partake of the contingence which enables us to remain ignorant of them. But there can be no knowledge of green without apprehension of times and places. Green presupposes here and there, and now and then. In other words, green presupposes the passage of nature in the form of a structure of events. It may be merely green associated vaguely with the head, green all about me; but green is not green apart from its signification of events with structural coherence, which are factors ex pressing the patience of fact for green.

A blade of grass is an object of another type which signifies nature as a passage of events. In this respect it only differs from green in so far as its contingent relations to some definite events are perhaps sharper and capable of more precise determination.

The significance of events is more complex. In the first place they are mutually significant of each other. The uniform significance of events thus becomes the uniform spatio-temporal structure of events. In this respect we have to dissent from Einstein who assumes for this structure casual heterogeneity arising from con tingent relations. Our consciousness also discloses to us this structure as uniformly stratified into durations which are complete nature during our specious presents. These stratifications exhibit the patience of fact for finite consciousness, but then they are in truth charac ters of nature and not illusions of consciousness.

Returning to the significance of events, we see that

26 THE RELATEDNESS OF NATURE [OH

there is no such thing as an isolated event. Each event essentially signifies the whole structure. But further more, there is no such entity as a bare event. Each event also signifies objects, other than events which are in essential "relation to it. In other words the passage of an event exhibits objects which do not pass. I have termed the natural factors which are not events but are implicated in events ' objects,' and awareness of an object is what I have termed recognition. Thus green is an object and so is a blade of grass, and awareness of green or of a blade of grass is recognition. Thus an event signifies objects in mutual relations. The particular objects and their particular relations belong to the sphere of contingence ; but the event is essentially a 'field,' in the sense that without related objects there can be no event. On the other hand related objects signify events, and without such events there are no such objects.

The celebrated two-termed relationship of universals to the concrete particulars which they qualify is merely a particular example of the general doctrine of signifi cance and patience. The universals are significant of their particulars, and the particulars are factors ex hibiting the patience of fact for those universals.

But in the apparent world, that is to say, in the world of nature disclosed by sense-awareness, no example of the simple two-termed relationship of a universal signi fying its particular is to be found. Green appears to an observer in a situation distinct from that of the observer, but simultaneous with it. Thus there is essential refer ence to three simultaneous events, the event which is the bodily life of the observer, called the percipient event, and the event which is the so-called situation of the green at the time of observation, and to the time of

n] THE RELATEDNESS OF NATURE 27

observation which is nothing else than the whole of nature at that time. Under the obsession of the logical theory of universals and concrete particulars the per cipient event was suppressed, and the relation of green to its situation represented as universal qualifying par ticular. It was then noted that this relation only holds for the particular observer, and that furthermore account must be taken of contingent circumstances such as the transmission of something, which is not the colour green, from an antecedent situation to the percipient event.

This process, of first presupposing a two-termed re lation and then finding that it is not true, has led to the bifurcation which places green in the observer's mind, qualifying a particular also in the observer's mind ; while the whole mental process has some undetermined rela tion to another system of entities variously described either as an independent physical universe in some causal relation to mind or as a conceptual model.

I have argued elsewhere in detail that this result is untenable. Here I will only remark that if we incline to adopt the physical universe, we can find no shred of evidence for it, since everything apparent for conscious ness has been accounted for as being in the observer's mind; while, if we turn to the conceptual model, it is also the model for the same consciousness. Accordingly whichever choice we make there will be no shred of evidence for anything other than the play of that con sciousness at one moment of self-realisation. For recol lection and anticipation are merely the play of immediate consciousness. Thus on either alternative, solipsism only is left and very little of that.

Meanwhile the whole difficulty has arisen from the initial error of forcing the complex relations between

28 THE RELATEDNESS OF NATURE [OH

green and the structure of events into the inadequate form of a two-termed relation.

Yet after all the search for universals to qualify events in the simple two-termed manner does represent a justifiable demand. We want to know what any par ticular event A is in itself apart from its reference to other events. By this I mean, we want to determine how A can enter into a two- termed relation of contrast with any other factor X without having necessarily to enlarge the relationship by including other events B, C, D, by way of determining A. For example, the colour green is in itself different from red, and we do not have to specify green or red by their diverse relation ships amid events in order to appreciate their contrast. Now we want to do much the same thing for events, so as to feel that an event has a character of its own. We have seen that the immediate objects of the apparent world such as colours do not satisfy the requisite conditions since their reference to events involves the re lations of the percipient event to the so-called situation. I call such objects of immediate appearance, sense- objects. Colours, sounds, smells, touches, pushes, bodily feelings, are sense-objects. But after all, the way we do connect these sense -objects, as I call them, with their situations shows that awareness of an event carries with it apprehension of that event as patient of a character qualifying it individually. In fact every event signifies a character for itself alone, but what exactly that character may be lies within the sphere of con tingency and is not disclosed in our immediate conscious ness of the apparent world. I will call such a character an adjective of its event. An adjective marks a break down in relativity by the very simplicity of the two-

ii] THE KELATEDNESS OF NATURE 29

termed relation it involves. The discovery of these missing adjectives is the task of natural science. The primary aim of science is to contract the sphere of con tingency by discovering adjectives of events such that the history of the apparent world in the future shall be the outcome of the apparent world in the past. There obviously is some such dependence, and it is the pur pose of science to express this dependence in terms of adjectives qualifying events. In order to understand this procedure of science, there are three concepts which we must understand. They are

(i) The structure of the four dimensional continuum, (ii) Pervasive adjectives and adjectival particles, * (iii) The atomic field of an adjectival particle. I will conclude this lecture by considering them in order.

(i) The structure of the continuum of events

This structure is four-dimensional, so that any event is a four-dimensional hyper-volume in which time is the fourth dimension. But we should not conceive an event as space and time, but as a unit from which space and time are abstracts.

An event with all its dimensions ideally restricted is called an 'event-particle/ and an event with only one dimension of finite extension is called a 'route' or 'path/ I will not in this lecture discuss the meaning of this ideal restriction. I have investigated it elsewhere under the name of 'extensive abstraction.'

The structure is uniform because of the necessity for knowledge that there be a system of uniform relatedness, in terms of which the contingent relations of natural factors can be expressed. Otherwise we can know

30 THE RELATEDNESS OF NATURE [OH

nothing until we know everything. If P be any event- particle, a moment through P is a system of event- particles representing all nature instantaneously con temporaneous with P. According to the classical view of time there can be only one such moment. According to the modern view there can be an indefinite number of alternative moments through P, each corresponding to a different meaning for time and space. A moment is an instantaneous three-dimensional section of nature and is the entity indicated when we speak of a moment of time.

The aggregate of event-particles lying on moments through P will be called the region co-present with P. The remainder of the four-dimensional continuum is divided by the co-present region into two regions, one being P's past and the other being P's future. The three- dimensional boundary between P's past and P's co- present region is P's causal past, and the corresponding boundary between P's future and P's co-present region is P's causalfuture. The remaining portion of P's future is P's kinematic future.

A route lying entirely in one moment is called a spatial route, and a route which lies entirely in the past and future of each one of its event-particles is called a historical* route.

(ii) Pervasive adjectives and adjectival particles

We gain great simplicity of explanation, without loss of any essential considerations by confining our con sideration of events to routes. These routes are of course not true events, but merely ideal limits with only one dimensional extension remaining.

* I borrow the term 'historical' from Prof. C. D. Broad.

II]

THE RELATEDNESS OF NATURE

31

32 THE RELATEDNESS OF NATURE [CH

A factor will be said to be an adjective pervading a route when it is an adjective of every stretch of the route. Such a factor will be called a pervasive adjective, or uniform object. I think without being very certain that true pervasive adjectives are only to be found qualifying historical routes ; but that pervasive pseudo- adjectives also qualify spatial routes. The essential difference between time and space finds its illustration in the difference between these two different types of route.

As an illustration of pervasive adjectives, consider a mass-particle m. The enduring existence of this particle marks out a historical route amid the structure of events. In fact the mass-particle is merely a pervasive adjective of that route, since it is an adjective qualifying in the same sense every stretch of that route. But here a further explanation is necessary. The mass-particle as a pervasive adjective is a universal and has lost its concrete individuality.

Another mass-particle of the same mass pervading another historical route is the same pervasive adjective also qualifying every stretch of that other route. It follows that the separate concrete individualities of the two mass-particles arise from the separate individualities of their two historical routes. Thus a concrete mass- particle is the fusion of a pervasive adjective with the individuality of a historical route. We say that a mass- particle is situated at each event -particle of its historical route. I will call a pervasive adjective as qualifying a particular historical route an ' adjectival particle.' The principle underlying the conception of an adjectival particle is that the individual embodiment of character always involves process and that this process is here represented by the historical route.

ii] THE KELATEDNESS OF NATUKE 33

Spatial routes cannot be pervaded by mass- particles. Thus if a mass-particle of the same mass be situated at each event-particle of a spatial route, that route is not pervaded by the one adjective which is the same uni versal for each of the concrete mass-particles. In fact a stretch of the spatial route is qualified by quite a differ ent adjective, which represents the sum of the masses situated at the event-particles of the stretch. Accord ingly spatial routes and historical routes function quite differently in respect to the adjective 'mass w,' and thus illustrate the difference between the spread of space and the lapse of time.

There are however pseudo-adjectives which do pervade spatial routes. Consider a sense-object, such as the colour red. It is not a true adjective of its situation, since there is always a necessary reference to a per cipient event. But for the one observer conscious of the natural relations of that percipient event, who is pre supposing this reference to his bodily life as a condition for appearance, the colour red is an adjective of its situation. But any part of its situation is also red, neither more nor less so than the whole enduring patch of red. Thus red pervades its situation. However I have already argued at length that sense-objects are not true adjectives. They simulate adjectives for an observer who in his intellectual analysis of the circumstances forgets to mention himself. Accordingly they may be called pervasive pseudo-adjectives.

The common material objects of perception, such as chairs, stones, planets, trees, etc., are adjectival bodies pervading the historical events which they qualify. In so expressing myself, I have gone beyond the ideal simplicity of a route, and the terms 'pervasion' and w. R. 3

34 THE RELATEDNESS OF NATURE [CH

'historical event' require, strictly speaking, a more elaborate explanation than I have yet given. In this lecture however it is unnecessary to undertake the task, and I need only refer to my Principles of Natural Knowledge where the requisite definitions are given in connection with uniform objects.

(iii) The atomic field of an adjectival particle

Science has been driven to have recourse to more precisely delimited adjectival objects than these ad jectival objects of perception. The standard types of such objects are mass-particles and electrons; and we will fall back on our ideal simplicities by conceiving them as adjectival particles defined, as above, for the ideal simplification of historical routes.

Now the essence of an adjectival object, whether it be the unprecise object of perception or the more precise object of science, is that it reduces the contingency of nature. It is an adjective of events which to some extent conditions the possibilities of apparent sense-objects.

It must be admitted that it is itself a contingent adjective. But owing to the simplicity of the relation of an adjective to its qualified substance, it involves a simpler contingency than the contingency of the complex relationships of sense-objects. In other words we are limiting contingency by the fixed conditions which are the laws of nature.

It is evident therefore that a scientific object must qualify future events. For otherwise the future contin gency is unaffected by it. In this a scientific object differs decisively from a sense-object viewed as a pseudo- adjective. A sense-object qualifies events in the present.

ii] THE RELATEDNESS OF NATURE 35

It is confined to a spatial region with the minimum of historicity requisite for the duration of the present. Whereas the scientific object qualifies a region extending from the present into the future. Thus the seemingly contingent play of the senses is controlled by the conditions introduced by its dependence upon the qualification of events introduced by scientific objects. A scientific object qualifies the future in two ways, (a) by its permanence and (b) by its field.

Let us take the permanence first. The permanence of an adjectival particle lets us know that there will be some historical route pervaded by that particle. It does not in itself tell us more than that some pervaded route will stretch into the future from the situation in the present. The permanence of the unique particle is nothing else than the continuity of the unique historical route, and its pervasion by the adjectival particle.

The further laws of physical science represent the further conditions which determine, or partially deter mine, the particular historical routes pervaded by these adjectival particles. The most simple expression of such a law consists in associating an atomic field with each adjectival particle as situated in each one of the event- particles of ifys pervaded route. Again this association of the field represents another eruption of contingency, but also again this contingency is of a simple defined type. The field of an adjectival particle m at a situation P is a limited region stretching from P into P's futurity. This region is qualified by an adjective dependent upon m and P only. For this simple type of law, the only limited region which can satisfy this demand is the three- dimensional boundary region between P's co-present and P's kinematic future. I have called this region P's

3—2

36 THE RELATEDNESS OF NATURE [CH

causal future. Accordingly the field of m at P must be P's causal future. Expressing this statement in terms of one consistent meaning for time and its associated- permanent space, we first note that P consists of a point SP at a time tp, and m situated in P means m at the point SP at the time tr. The causal future of P means those points SB, at times tB [i.e. those event-particles such as B], reached by a physical character due to m, and starting from SP at time tp and arriving at SB at time tB9 and travelling with the critical maximum velocity c.

Experiment shows that this critical maximum velocity is a near approximation to the velocity of light in vacuo, but its definition in no way depends upon any reference to light. Thus the adjectival character of the field of m Sit P consists in the correlated physical characters of the different event-particles of the field. The whole conception is practically the familiar one of tubes of force, with one exception. A tube of force is con ceived statically as a simultaneous character stretching through space. This statical conception destroys the true individuality of a tube by piecing together frag ments of different tubes. As we pass along a tube radiating from SP we keep to the same tube by allowing for the lapse of time required by the velocity c.

The peculiar correlation of adjectives attaching to the various event-particles of the field of m at P will depend upon the particular contingent law which science con jectures to be the true expression of m's physical status.

There are, also, less simple laws of nature for which the influence of the contingent configurations of other adjectival particles will be essential factors. Such laws will in general involve the deflection of the field of m at P from P's causal future into P's kinematic future. The

ii] THE RELATEDNESS OF NATURE 37

region will be dependent upon the fields of the other relevant adjectival particles. It is evident that with such laws we are rapidly drifting towards the difficulty of having to know everything before knowing any thing.

I will call such fields ' obstructed fields.' Differential equations help us here. But even their aid would be unavailing unless we could approximate from the first assumption of unobstructed fields for the adjectival particles producing the obstruction. In this way the influence of gravitation upon the electromagnetic field can be calculated and vice versa.

This account of the status of scientific objects com pletely changes the status of the ether; from that presumed in nineteenth century science. In the classical doctrine the ether is the shy agent behind the veil : in the account given here the ether is exactly the apparent world, neither more nor less. The apparent world dis closes itself to us as the ingression of sense-objects amid events. In this statement the term 'ingression' is used for the complex relationship of those abstract elements of the world, such as sense-objects, which are devoid of becomingness and extension, to those other more concrete elements (events) which retain becomingness and extension. But a bare event is a mere abstraction. Events are disclosed as involved in this relationship of ingression. This disclosure is our perceptual vision of the apparent world. We now ask on behalf of science whether we cannot simplify the regulative principles discerned in this apparent world by treating events as something more than relata in the relationship of in gression. Cannot we discern true Aristotelian qualities as attaching to the events ? Is not each event something

38 THE RELATEDNESS OF NATURE [CH

in itself, apart from its status as a mere relatum in the relationship of ingression \ The apparent world itself gives an answer, partially in the affirmative. Chairs, tables, and perceptual objects generally, have lost the complexity of ingression, and appear as the required Aristotelian adjectives of some events. Their appearance involves that borderline where sense-aware ness is fusing with thought. It is difficult to make any account of them precise. In fact, for the purpose of science they suffer from incurable vagueness. But they mark the focal centres to be used as the radiating centres for an exact account of true Aristotelian adjec tives without any of those qualifications here referred to as * vagueness.' The events of the apparent world as thus qualified by the exact adjectives of science are what we call the ' ether.' Accordingly in my previous work, The Principles of Natural Knowledge, I have phrased it in this way, that the older ' ether of stuff' is here supplanted by an * ether of events.'

This line of thought, supplanting 'stuff* by 'events,' and conceiving events as involving process and exten sion and contingent qualities and as primarily relata in the relationship of ingression, is a recurrence to Des cartes' views with a difference. Descartes, like the rest of the world at that time, completely dissociated space and time. He assigned extension to space, and process to time. It is true that time involves extension of some sort, but that does not seem to have coloured his philosophy. Now according to Descartes 'extension' is an abstract from the more concrete concept of ' stuff.' He, like the rest of the world, considers stuff as being separable from the concept of ' process,' so that stuff fully realises itself at an instant, without duration.

ii] THE RELATEDNESS OF NATURE 39

Space is thus a property of stuff, and accordingly follows stuff in being essentially dissociated from time. He there fore deduces that space is an essential timeless plenum. It is merely an abstract from the concrete world of appearance at an instant. If there be no stuff to appear, there can be no space.

Now re-write this Cartesian account of space, sub stituting 'events' (which retain 'process') for 'stuff' (which has lost ' process '). You then return to my ac count of space-time, as an abstract from events which are the ultimate repositories of the varied individualities in nature. But space as pure extension, dissociated from process, and time as pure serial process, are correlative abstractions which can be made in different ways, each way representing a real property of nature. In this manner the alternative spaces and the alternative times, which have already been mentioned, are seen to be justifiable conceptions, according to the account of the immediate deliverances of awareness here given, provided that our experience can be thereby explained.

Mere deductive logic, whether you clothe it in mathe matical symbols and phraseology or whether you enlarge its scope into a more general symbolic technique, can never take the place of clear relevant initial concepts of the meaning of your symbols, and among symbols I include words. If you are dealing with nature, your meanings must directly relate to the immediate facts of observation. We have to analyse first the most general characteristics of things observed, and then the more casual contingent occurrences. There can be no true physical science which looks first to mathematics for the provision of a conceptual model. Such a procedure is to repeat the errors of the logicians of the middle-ages.

CHAPTER III

EQUALITY

THE criticism of the meanings of simple obvious state ments assumes especial importance when any large reorganisation of current ideas is in progress. The up heaval produced by the Einstein doctrine of relativity is a case in point. It demands a careful scrutiny of the fundamental ideas of physical science in general and of mathematical physics in particular. I propose therefore in this lecture to take one of the simplest mathematical notions which we all come across when we start mathe matics in our early school life and to ask what it means.

The example I have chosen is the notion of ' equality.' There is hardly a page or a paragraph of any mathe matical book which does not employ this idea. It appears in geometry in the more specialised form of congruence.

If I am not mistaken, clear notions on equality are of decisive importance for the sound reconstruction of mathematical physics. Congruence is a more special term than equality, being confined to mean the quanti tative equality of geometrical elements. Equality is also closely allied to the idea of quantity; but here again I think that equality touches the more general ideas. The consideration of quantity necessarily introduces that of measurement. In fact the scope of a discussion on quantity may be defined by the question, How is measurement possible? Lastly, equality has an obvious affinity with identity. Some philosophers in considering

CH m] EQUALITY 41

the foundations of mathematics would draw no distinc tion between the two. In certain usages of equality this may be the case. But it cannot be the whole truth. For if it were, the greater part of mathematics would consist of a reiteration of the tautologous statement that a thing is itself. We are interested in equality because diversity has crept in.

In fact a discussion of equality embraces in its scope congruence, quantity, measurement, identity and diversity. The importance of equality was discovered by the Greeks. We all know Euclid's axiom, 'Things that are equal to the same thing are also equal to one another' (TO, TO) avrq) Lcra /cat aAA^Xoi? tcn\v icra). This axiom deserves its fame, in that it is one of the first efforts to clarify thought by an accurate statement of premises habitually assumed. It is the most conspicuous example of the decisive trend of Greek thought towards rigid accuracy in detailed expression, to which we owe our modern philosophy, our modern science, and the creeds of the Christian Church. But grateful as we are to the Greeks for this axiom and for the whole state of mind which it indicates, we cannot withdraw it from philosophic scrutiny. The whole import of the axiom depends on the meaning of the word tcro?, equal. What do we mean when we say that one thing is equal to another? Suppose we explain by stating that 'equal' means 'equal in magnitude,' that is to say, the things are quantities of the same magnitude. But what is a quantity? If we define it as having the property of being measurable in terms of a unit, we are thrown back upon the equality of different examples of the same unit. It is evident that we are in danger of soothing ourselves with a vicious circle whereby equality is

42 EQUALITY [CH

explained by reference to quantity and quantity by reference to equality.

Let us first drop the special notion of quantitative equality and consider the most general significance of that notion. The relation of equality denotes a possible diversity of things related but an identity of character qualifying them. It is convenient for technical facility in the arrangement of deductive trains of reasoning to allow that a thing is equal to itself, so that equality includes identity as a special case. But this is a mere matter of arbitrary definition.

The important use of equality is when there is diversity of things related and identity of character. This identity of character must not be mere identity of the complete characters. For in that case, by the principle of the identity of indiscernables, the equal things would be necessarily identical.

Accordingly when we write

A=B

we are referring implicitly to some character and asserting that A and B both possess it. The assertion of equality is therefore generally couched in a highly elliptical form since the expression of the character in question is often omitted. This is a source of most of the confused thinking which haunts discussion on this subject. Let us remedy our notation so as to rid it of its misleading ellipticity. Let (cl}c2, . . . , cn) denote a class of characters clt ca, ... , cn, such as colour for example. Then we write

A=B-*(cl9ca, ..., cn)

to mean that A and B both possess the same character out of the set (clt c2, ... , cn); and we write

tfa.c,, ...,cn)

m] EQUALITY 43

to mean that different characters out of the set apply to A and B respectively. Our notation still has the defect of implying that the class of characters is a finite or at least an enumerable class. Let us therefore take y to represent this class, so that

means that the same member of the class y qualifies both A and B\ and

means that one member of y qualifies A and that another member of y qualifies B. I will call y the 'qualifying class.'

It is now evident that

A=B-*y and Z?=(7->y

implies that A = (7—>y.

This is evidently a general rendering of Euclid's first axiom.

But we are not yet at the end of our discussion. In the first place, we cannot yet prove that

A=B-*y and A^B-*y

are incompatible with each other. For we have not yet excluded the case that more than one character of the set y may attach either to A or to B or to both. For example if ^ and c2 are members of y, both attaching to A, but only cx attaching to B, then both

A=B-*y and

Accordingly we must re-define the meaning of our

44 EQUALITY [CH

symbols by introducing the additional limitation that

A=B-*y and A^B-^y

both mean that A and B each possess one and only one character of the class y. It is well to note that the two propositions represented by these symbolic statements are only contraries to each other. For though they cannot both be true, they will both be false if either A or B does not possess any character out of the qualifying class y. For example if A does not possess any such quality or if it possesses two such qualities, then

A=A->y and A =j= A -> y

are both false. This example also illustrates the sharp distinction between equality and mere identity.

In this most general sense of equality, the notion of 'matching/ in the sense in which colours match, might with advantage replace equality, so that we should

interpret

A=B-+y and A =f B -> y

as meaning respectively

'A matches B in respect to the qualities y' and

'A does not match B in respect to the qualities y! This verbal statement in its common meaning pre supposes our three conditions :

(i) that A and B each possess one of the qualities y,

(ii) that neither^ nor B possesses more than one such quality,

(iii) that A and B possess the same one of the

m] EQUALITY 45

qualities y, and (in the second case) that A and B do not possess the same one of the qualities.

The set of entities such as A and B possessing one and only one of the qualities of the class y will be said to form the 'qualified class for y,' and we have already named y the 'qualifying class.'

Congruence. Congruence is a subspecies of the general type of the equality relation. Let us start with the simplest example and consider a one-dimensional space. The points of this space are terms interconnected by a relation which arranges them in serial order with the ordinary continuity of the Dedekindian type. The points may be connected by other relations which sort them out in other ways ; but when we say that they form a one-dimensional space, we are thinking of one definite relation which produces the continuous serial order, both ways infinite.

Now in the particularising of the equality relation so as to produce a congruence relation for this space, we first demand that, if y be the qualifying class, the class qualified by y must be composed of all the finite stretches of the space. Thus the terms A, B, etc. in the previous explanation of equality are now stretches of the serial space, and every finite stretch belongs to the qualified class. It will be convenient to confine attention to those stretches which include their two end-points. Let two stretches which do not overlap, except that they have one end-point in common, be called adjoined stretches, or stretches adjoined at that end-point.

Now the conditions which have to be fulfilled in order that this type of equality may reckon as a congruence are:

46 EQUALITY [CB

(i) If A be any stretch and p any point, there ar^ two stretches P1 and P2 adjoined at p, such that

and A = P2 -> y.

In other words, from a given point p stretches of ai assigned length can be measured in either direction.

(ii) If P and Q are two stretches, and P contains Q, then

In other words, the whole is unequal to its part.

(iii) If P and Q be two stretches, and P be composed of the adjoint stretches Px and P2, and Q of the adjoint stretches Ql and Qz, and furthermore if

and P2 = Qz -> y,

then P =Q > y.

In other words, if equals be added to equals the wholes are equal.

(iv) If the first clause of the hypothesis of (iii) hold, and furthermore if

P= Q -»y

and P1=Q1-+ y,

then Pn=Q2—> y.

In other words, if equals be taken from equals the remainders are equal.

(v) The axiom that the whole is greater than its part suffers from the difficulty that we have not defined what we mean by 'greater than.' Our condition (ii) states that the whole is unequal to its part. But the idea of 'greater than' really follows from the condition which we wish to express. I think that the missing condition is best stated thus :

in] EQUALITY 47

, Let A and B be two stretches of which one contains ,he other, so that either A contains B or B contains A, md let H and K be two other stretches with the same property in regard to each other. Also let

Then if H contains K, it also follows that A contains B. The point of this condition is that we exclude the crosswise equality in which A is congruent to a part of H and H to a part of A.

Then the idea of any stretch P being greater than any stretch Q must be defined to mean that there is a stretch H containing a part K such that

Thus the verbal form, the whole is greater than its part, becomes a mere tautology. The true point being first our condition (ii) that the whole is unequal to any of its parts, and our condition (v) which excludes the crosswise equality of wholes to parts.

The theory of 'numerical measurement depends upon three additional conditions which can be conveniently preceded by some definitions. Let a sequence of n successively adjoined stretches AL9 A.2, ... , An, which is such that

Ap = Aq->y, [p, 2 = 1,2, ...,?i]

be called a ' stretch sequence for y.' Let each individual stretch of the sequence be called a 'component stretch' of the sequence, and let the stretch which is composed of all the stretches of the sequence be called the 'resultant stretch' of the sequence.

48 EQUALITY [CH

Furthermore if c be the member of y which charac terises each component stretch of the sequence of n stretches, let nc be the symbol for the member of y which characterises the resultant stretch of the sequence.

Also if cf be an alternative symbol for nc, let - cf be an

n

alternative symbol for c.

The three conditions are :

(vi) If A be any stretch and n be any integer, then a stretch sequence for y can be found composed of n members such that A is its resultant.

(vii) If A and B be any two coterminous stretches, and A be part of B, then we can find an integer n such that there exists a stretch sequence for y of n terms such that A is its first term and B is part of the re sultant of the sequence.

(viii) If A be any stretch and n any integer, then A is a member in any assigned ordinal position of two stretch sequences for y of n terms, the two sequences running in opposed directions.

The condition (vii) is the axiom of Archimedes.

It is evident that we may conceive y as the class of magnitudes and the stretches as the class of concrete quantities. The difference between a magnitude and a concrete quantity is the difference between the length, called a yard, and the particular concrete instance which is in the custody of the Warden of the Standards.

It is not necessary to plunge further into the exact analysis of the theory of extensive quantity. The dis cussion has been carried far enough to make it evident that the qualifying class y, which is the class of magni tudes, is simply a class of qualities which happen to be sorted out among the qualified class (which in the above example was a class of stretches) in such a way that,

in] EQUALITY 49

when one member of y has been taken as the standard of reference, the unit, all the other members of y can be described in terms of it by means of real numbers. But a quality which belongs to the set y is in itself in no way otherwise distinguished from any other quality of things. Quantity arises from a distribution of qualities which in a certain definite way has regard to the peculiar fact that in certain cases two extended spatio-temporal elements together form a third such element. In fact the 'qualifying' qualities are distri buted among extended things with a certain regard to their property of extension. Also it is evident that two stretches A and B which are equal for one quali fying class y may be unequal for another qualifying class y.

If we apply this doctrine to the classical theory of space and time, we find, following Sophus Lie's analysis, that there are an indefinite number of qualifying classes y, y, y", etc., which for the case of three-dimensional space generate relations of congruence among spatial elements, and that each such set of congruence relations is inconsistent with any other such set.

For the case of time the opposite trouble arises. Tune in itself, according to the classical theory, presents us with no qualifying class at all on which a theory of congruence can be founded.

This breakdown of the uniqueness of congruence for space and of its very existence for time is to be con trasted with the fact that mankind does in truth agree on a congruence system for space and on a congruence system for time which are founded on the direct evidence of its senses. We ask, why this pathetic trust in the yard- measure and the clock? The truth is that we have observed something which the classical theory does not explain.

W. R. 4

50 EQUALITY [CH

It is important to understand exactly where the diffi culty lies. It is often wrongly conceived as depending on the inexactness of all measurements in regard to very small quantities. According to our methods of observa tion we may be correct to a hundredth, or a thousandth, or a millionth of an inch. But there is always a margin left over within which we cannot measure. However this character of inexactness is not the difficulty in question.

Let us suppose that our measurements can be ideally exact; it will be still the case that if one man uses one qualifying class y and the other man uses another qualifying class S, and if they both admit the standard yard kept in the exchequer chambers to be their unit of measurement, they will disagree as to what other distances places should be judged to be equal to that standard distance in the exchequer chambers. Nor need their disagreement be of a negligible character. For example, the man who uses the qualifying class y might be in agreement with the rest of us, who are also using y, and the other man who uses S might also be a well- trained accurate observer. But in his measurement the distance from York to Edinburgh might come out at exactly one yard.

But no one, who is not otherwise known to be a lunatic, is apt to make such a foolish mistake.

The conclusion is that when we cease to think of mere abstract mathematics and proceed to measure in the realm of nature, we choose our qualifying class y for some reason in addition to the mere fact that the various characters included in y are sorted among stretches so as to satisfy the conditions for congruence which I have jotted down above.

When we say that two stretches match in respect to

in] EQUALITY 51

length, what do we mean? Furthermore we have got to include time. When two lapses of time match in respect to duration, what do we mean? We have seen that measurement presupposes matching, so it is of no use to hope to explain matching by measurement.

We have got to dismiss from our minds all considera tions of number and measurement and quantity, and simply concentrate attention on what we mean by matching in length.

It is an entirely different and subsequent considera tion as to whether length in this sense of the term is a class of qualities which is sorted out to stretches in accordance with the congruence conditions.

Our physical space therefore must already have a structure and the matching must refer to some qualifying class of qualities inherent in this structure. The only possible structure is that of planes and straight lines, such that stretches of straight lines can be conceived as composed of points arranged in order.

An additional factor of structure can be that of ordinary Euclidean parallelism. By this I mean that through any point outside a plane there is one and only one plane which does not intersect a given plane. You will observe that I have had to adopt what is termed Playfair's axiom for the definition of parallels. It is the only one which does not introduce some presupposition of congruence, either of length or angles. I draw your attention to the absolute necessity of defining our structure without the presupposition of congruence. If we fail in this respect our argument will be involved in a vicious circle.

With this definition of parallels it is now very easy to get some way in the explanation of what we mean

4-2

52

EQUALITY

[CH

by stretches matching in length. For since our structure includes parallels, it also includes parallelograms. Ac cordingly we can agree that the opposite sides of parallelograms match in length. It is then easy enough to show that we have a complete system of congruence for any one system of parallel stretches in space. This means that if there are any two stretches either on the same straight line or on parallel straight lines, we have a definitely determined numerical ratio of the length of one to the length of the other.

But we cannot go further and compare the lengths of two stretches which are not parallel, unless we in troduce some additional principle for the matching of lengths.

We can find this additional principle provided that we can define a right-angle without any appeal to the idea of congruence or equality. For let us anticipate such a definition independent of congruence.

8 D C

Let D be the midpoint of the stretch BC, and draw DA perpendicular to BC. Then our additional principle of matching shall be that AB is equal to AC. In this way we can compare the lengths of stretches which are not parallel, and the whole theory of congruence in space is established.

in] EQUALITY 53

But as yet we have not gone any way towards finding any theory for the congruence of lapses of time. Accord ingly if we are to explain how it is that in our observa tion of nature we all agree in our systems of space and time congruence, we have to explain what we mean by planes, and by right-angles, and how we should match lapses of time. We can omit straight lines from this catalogue, since they can be defined as the intersections of planes. We shall however have to explain how the points on straight lines come to be arranged in order.

When we are conscious of nature, what is it that we really observe? The obvious answer is that we perceive various material bodies, such as chairs, bricks, trees. We can touch them, see them and hear them. As I write I can hear the birds singing in a Berkshire garden in early spring.

In conformity with this answer, it is now fashionable and indeed almost universal to say that our notions of space merely arise from our endeavours to express the relations of these bodies to each other. I am sorry to appear pigheaded ; but, though I am nearly in a minority of one, I believe this answer to be entirely wrong. I will explain my reasons.

Are these material bodies really the ultimate data of perception, incapable of further analysis?

If they are, I at once surrender. But I submit that plainly they have not this ultimate character. My allu sion to the birds singing was made not because I felt poetical, but to warn you that we were being led into a difficulty. What I immediately heard was the song. The birds only enter perception as a correlation of more ultimate immediate data of perception, among which for my consciousness their song is dominant.

V

54 \ \EQUALITY [CH

Material bodies only enter my consciousness as a representation of a certain coherence of the sense-objects such as colours, sounds and touches. But these sense- objects at once proclaim themselves to be adjectives (pseudo-adjectives, according to the previous chapter) of events. It is not mere red that we see, but a red patch in a definite place enduring through a definite time. The red is an adjective of the red time and place. Thus nature appears to us as the continuous passage of instantaneous three-dimensional spatial spreads, the temporal passage adding a fourth dimension. Thus nature is stratified by time. In fact passage in time is of the essence of nature, and a body is merely the coherence of adjectives qualifying the same route through the four- dimensional space-time of events.

But as the result of modern observations we have to admit that there are an indefinite number of such modes of time stratification.

However, this admission at once yields an expla nation of the meaning of the instantaneous spatial extension of nature. For it explains this extension as merely the exhibition of the different ways in which simultaneous occurrences function in regard to other time-systems.

I mean that occurrences which are simultaneous for one time-system appear as spread out in three dimen sions because they function diversely for other time- systems. The extended space of one time-system is merely the expression of properties of other time- systems.

According to this doctrine, a moment of time is nothing else than an instantaneous spread of nature. Thus let tlt t2, t3 be three moments of time according to

Ill]

EQUALITY

55

one time-system, and let Tlt T2, T3 be three moments of time according to another time-system. The inter sections of pairs of moments in diverse time-systems are planes in each instantaneous three-dimensional space. In the diagram each continuous line accordingly sym bolises a three-dimensional space; and the intersections of continuous lines, such as A or B or (7, symbolise

ft fe

planes. Thus ^ and Tl are each a three-dimensional space, and A is a plane in either space.

Parallelism is the reflection into an instantaneous space of one time-system of the property of moments of some other system. Thus A and B are parallel planes in tlt since Tl and jT2 are moments of the same system which is not the system to which ^ belongs.

56 EQUALITY [OH

But when we talk of space we are not usually thinking of the instantaneous fact of immediate perception. We are thinking of an enduring scheme of extension within which all these instantaneous facts are fitted. It follows that we ought to be able to find a meaning for the idea of a permanent space in connection with each time- system.

This conception must arise from our immediate obser vations of motion and rest. Both rest and motion have no meaning in connection with one mere instantaneous space. In such a space everything is where it is and there is an instantaneous end to it ; to be succeeded by another instantaneous space. But motion and rest at once warn us that our perception involves something more.

The instantaneous moment is merely an ideal limit of perception. Have you ever endeavoured to capture the instantaneous present? It eludes you, because in truth there is no such entity among the crude facts of our experience. Our present experience is an enduring fact within which we discriminate a passage of nature. Now within this enduring fact we observe rest and motion. A body at rest in the space of our observation is tracing out a certain historical route intersecting the moments of our time-system in a sequence of instan taneous points. This route is what we mean by a point of the permanent space of our time-system. Thus each time-system has its own space with its own points, and these permanent points are loci of instantaneous points.

The paradoxes of relativity arise from the fact that we have not noticed that when we change our time- system we change the meaning of time, the meaning of space and the meaning of points of space (conceived as permanent).

in] EQUALITY 57

Now the route of a small body at rest in the space of a time-system, that is to say, a point of that time-system, has a certain symmetry in respect to the successive in stantaneous spaces of that system, which is expressed for us by the perception of lack of change of position. This symmetry is the basis of the definition of rectangularity.

If the body be at rest in the space of the time-system t, it is moving in a straight line in the space of another time-system T. This permanent straight line intersects any moment of T, say T19 in an instantaneous straight line ^ (say). Then /> is perpendicular to the series of instantaneous parallel planes in which the moments of system t intersect T^. In other words the planes to which motion is perpendicular are the planes of inter section with the moments of that time-system for whose space that motion would be represented as rest.

We have thus defined both parallelism and perpen dicularity without reference to congruence, but in terms of immediate data of perception. Furthermore, the parallelism of the moments of one time-system enables us to extend parallelism to time as also expressing the relation to each other of permanent points of the same time-system. It thus follows that we now possess a structure in terms of which congruence can be defined. This means that there will be a class of qualities y one and only one of which attaches to any stretch on a straight line or on a point, such that matching in respect to this quality is what we mean by congruence.

The thesis that I have been maintaining is that measurement presupposes a perception of matching in quality. Accordingly in examining the meaning of any particular kind of measurement we have to ask, What is the quality that matches?

58 EQUALITY [CH

Furthermore, in applying this doctrine to measure ments in space and time, I have maintained that the things whose qualities match are events. In other words, I maintained that it is events that are congruent, and that spatial congruence and temporal congruence are merely special instances of this fundamental congruence. In conformity with this doctrine I also maintain that space and time are merely the exhibition of relations between events.

The usual opinion, or at any rate the more usual mode of expression, is that space and time are relations between the material objects implicated in events. It is difficult to understand how time can be a relation between two permanent objects. Also with the modern assimilation of time and space, this difficulty in respect to time also attaches to space. Furthermore, I hold that these per manent objects are nothing else than adjectives of events. It follows that a yard measure is merely a device for making evident the spatial congruence of the events in which it is implicated.

The divergence between the two points of view as to space-time, that is to say, as to whether it exhibits re lations between events or relations between objects in events is really of the utmost importance in the stage of physical science. If it be a relatedness between events, it has the character of a systematic uniform relatedness between events which is independent of the contingent adjectives of events. In this case we must reject Ein stein's view of a heterogeneity in space-time. But if space-time be a relatedness between objects, it shares in the contingency of objects, and may be expected to acquire a heterogeneity from the contingent character of objects. I cannot understand what meaning can be

in] EQUALITY 59

assigned to the distance of the sun from Sirius if the very nature of space depends upon casual intervening objects which we know nothing about. Unless we start with some knowledge of a systematically related structure of space-time we are dependent upon the contingent relations of bodies which we have not examined and cannot prejudge.

Furthermore, how time is to be got from the relations of permanent bodies completely puzzles me. And yet the moderns assimilate time with space. I have never seen even the beginning of an explanation of the meaning of the usual phraseology.

I have already reiterated, that measurement presup poses a structure yielding definite stretches which, in some sense inherent in the structure, match each other; and I have explained the type of structure which is formed by our space-time.

The essence of this structure is that it is stratified in many different ways by different time-systems. This is a very peculiar idea which is the product of the speculations of the last fifteen years or so. We owe the whole conception notably to Einstein. I do not agree with his way of handling his discovery. But I have no doubt as to its general correctness. It is at first sight somewhat of a shock to think that other beings may slice nature into time-sections in a different way to what we do. In fact we have differences even among ourselves which luckily are quite imperceptible. How ever if we allow this possibility we not only explain many modern delicate experiments, but we also obtain explanations of what we mean by the spatial extension in three dimensions, and by planes and straight lines, and parallels and right-angles. We also obtain a definite

60 EQUALITY [CH m

meaning for the matching which is the basis of our con gruence. The explanation is too sweeping to be put aside. Our whole geometry is merely the expression of the ways in which different events are implicated in different time-systems.

I have also hitherto omitted to point out that all order in space is merely the expression of order in time. For a series of parallel planes in the space of our time is merely the series of intersections with a series of moments of another time-system. Thus the order of the parallel planes is merely the time-order of the moments of this other system.

I must stop now. We started from the simplest idea which meets every child at the beginning of his or her schooldays. I mean the idea of equality.

We asked what it meant. We have then been led on and on, till we have found ourselves plunged in the abstruse modern speculations concerning the character of the Universe. They are not really very difficult. I call them abstruse because they deal with questions which we do not ordinarily think about. It is therefore a strain on our imaginations to follow the line of thought. But when we have once allowed the possibility of different meanings for time in nature, the argument is a straight forward deduction of the consequences.

CHAPTER TV

SOME PRINCIPLES OF PHYSICAL SCIENCE

IT is my ambition in this lecture to discuss some general principles of mathematical physics, and to illustrate them by their application to the problem of the gravi tational field. In a sense such a discussion should form the first chapter of the science, but it is that first chapter which is studied last.

The Apparent World. It would be easy to quote an imposing array of authorities, almost a consensus of authorities, in support of the thesis that the subject matter of physical science is composed of things observed by the senses. Such things are sights, sounds, touches, bodily feelings, shapes, distances, and their mutual rela tions. I will call the whole assemblage of them the 'apparent world.' Natural science is therefore the study of the interconnections of the things forming the ap parent world.

This profession of the motive of science seems however in sharp contradiction to its actual achievement. The molecular theory, the wave theory of light, and finally the electromagnetic theory of things in general have, as it seems, set up for scientific investigation a society of entities, such as ether, molecules, and electrons, which are intrinsically incapable of direct observation. When Sir Ernest Rutherford at Cambridge knocks a molecule to pieces, he does not see a molecule or an electron. What he observes is a flash of light. There is at most a parallelism between his observation and the conjectural molecular catastrophe.

62 SOME PRINCIPLES OF PHYSICAL SCIENCE [OH

I suggest to you that, unless we are careful in our formulation of principles, the outcome of this train of thought is apt to be unsatisfactory and very misleading to scientific imagination. The apparent world becomes an individual psychological reaction to the stimulus of an entirely disparate interplay of electrons and ether. The whole of it is in the same boat. There is no prin ciple by which we can assign for some of it any indepen dence of individual psychology superior to that of the remainder.

On this theory we must entirely separate psychological time, space, external perceptions, and bodily feelings from the scientific world of molecular interaction. This strange world of science dwells apart like the gods of Epicurus, except that it has the peculiar property of inducing our minds to play upon us the familiar antics of our senses.

If we are to avoid this unfortunate bifurcation, we must construe our knowledge of the apparent world as being an individual experience of something which is more than personal. Nature is thus a totality including individual experiences, so that we must reject the dis tinction between nature as it really is and experiences of it which are purely psychological. Our experiences of the apparent world are nature itself.

Two-fold Cognisance. We have a two-fold cognisance of nature, and I will name the two factors of this ex perience 'cognisance by adjective' and 'cognisance by relatedness.'

Think of yourself as saying, 'There is a red patch.' You are affirming redness of something, and you are primarily conscious of that something because of its redness. In other words, the redness exhibits to you the

iv] SOME PRINCIPLES OF PHYSICAL SCIENCE 63

something which is red. This is cognisance by adjective, red being the adjective. But your experience has gone further than mere cognisance by adjective. Your know ledge is not merely of something which is red. The patch is there and it endures while you are observing it. Thus you are cognisant of it as having spatio-temporal position, and by this we mean a certain type of related- ness to the rest of nature which is thereby involved in our particular experience. This knowledge of nature arising from its interconnectedness by spatio-temporal relations is cognisance by relatedness.

For example, the physiological account of the function of the brain as determining the conditions of external perception presupposes that the events of the brain signify the totality of contemporaneous space. Again the disclosure of space behind the looking-glass as qualified by images situated in it exhibits the fact that the events in front of the glass are significant of con temporaneous space behind it. Also we know that there is space inside the closed cupboard.

Nature is an abstraction from something more con crete than itself which must also include imagination, thought, and emotion. This abstraction is characterised by the systematic coherency of its interconnections disclosed in cognisance by relatedness. Thus the sub stances of nature which have the cognised adjectives as their qualities are also the things in nature connected by the cognised relatedness. Nature is delimited as the field of this closed system of related things. Accordingly the ultimate facts of nature are events, and the essence of cognisance by relatedness is the ability to specify the event by time and by place. Dreams are ruled out by their inability to pass this test.

64 SOME PRINCIPLES OF PHYSICAL SCIENCE [CH

But an event can be specified in this way without its being the subject of direct cognisance by adjective. For example we can exactly specify a time and a place on the further surface of the moon, but we should very much like to know what is happening there. There is however a certain fullness in the dual cognisance both by adjec tive and by relatedness. I will use the term 'perception' for this full experience.

Mere cognisance by relatedness is essentially know ledge of an event merely by its spatio-temporal relations to other events which are perceived and thus form a framework of what is fully experienced. In this sense there is no cognisance by relatedness without perception.

It is not the case that the analysis of the adjectives of appearance attached to the events within any limited field of nature carries with it any certain knowledge of adjectives attached to other events in the rest of nature, or indeed of other such adjectives attached to those same events. I will refer to this fact by the phrase, the contingency of appearance.

On the other hand, though the character of time and space is not in any sense a priori, the essential related- ness of any perceived field of events to all other events requires that this relatedness of all events should con form to the ascertained disclosure derived from the limited field. For we can only know that distant events are spatio- temporally connected with the events imme diately perceived by knowing what these relations are. In other words, these relations must possess a systematic uniformity in order that we may know of nature as extending beyond isolated cases subjected to the direct examination of individual perception. I will refer to this fact by the phrase, the uniform significance of events.

iv] SOME PRINCIPLES OF PHYSICAL SCIENCE 65

Thus the constitutive character of nature is expressed by 'the contingency of appearance' and 'the uniform significance of events.' These laws express characters of nature disclosed respectively in cognisance by adjective and cognisance by relatedness. This doctrine leads to the rejection of Einstein's interpretation of his formulae, as expressing a casual heterogeneity of spatio-temporal warping, dependent upon contingent adjectives. ~The case of the yard-measure illustrates my meaning. It is a contingent adjective of the events where it is situated. Its spatio-temporal properties are entirely derived from the events which it qualifies. For example, its use depends on the recognition of simultaneity, so that we shall not observe its two ends at widely different times. But simultaneity concerns events. Also the mere self-identity of the yard-measure does not suffice for its use, since we also admit the continued identity of objects which shrink or expand. The yard-measure is merely a device for making evident obscure relations between those events in which it appears.

If congruence merely meant relations between con tingent adjectives of appearance, there would be no measurement of spatial distance or of temporal lapse without knowledge of actual intervening appearances, and no meaning for such distance in the absence of these adjectives. For example, the ' distance of the star Sirius ' would be a phrase without meaning.

You will have observed that in this doctrine of cog nisance by relatedness I am merely taking the old belief that we know of unbounded time and of unbounded space and am adapting it to my inversion which gives the supremacy to events and reduces time and space to mere relations between them.

W. R. 5

66 SOME PRINCIPLES OF PHYSICAL SCIENCE [CH

The Doctrine of Time. It follows from my refusal to bifurcate nature into individual experience and external cause that we must reject the distinction between psychological time which is personal and impersonal time as it is in nature. Two conclusions follow, of which the one is conservative, and indeed almost reactionary, and the other is paradoxical.

The conservative conclusion is that in cognisance by relatedness the apparent world is disclosed as stratified into a succession of strata which are subordinate totali ties of immediate experience. Each short duration of time is merely a total slab of nature disclosed as a totality in cognisance by relatedness, and for any individual ex perience partially disclosed in cognisance by adjective. There can be no other meaning for time, if we admit the position from which my argument has started. I will state the doctrine in this way, Time is a stratification of nature. Adherence to this doctrine is today the mark of a reactionary. I accept the term with the qualifi cation that it is reaction to the admission of obvious fact.

We now pass to the other conclusion which is para doxical. The assumption of the uniqueness of the tem poral stratification of nature has slipped into human thought. Certainly in each individual experience such uniqueness must be granted. But confessedly each individual experience is partial, and we cannot safely reason from partial experience to the limitation of the variety of nature. Accordingly the uniqueness of time succession for each of us does not guarantee its consis tency for all.

At this point I put by urgent metaphysical questions concerning any supposed distinction between past,

iv] SOME PRINCIPLES OF PHYSICAL SCIENCE 67

present, and future as to the character of their existence. Also I need not recall to your minds the reasons, based upon refined observations, for assuming the existence in nature of alternative time-systems entailing alternative systems of stratification.

I think that no one can study the evidence in its detail without becoming convinced that we are in the presence of one of the most profound reorganisations of scientific and philosophic thought. But so many con siderations are raised, so diverse in character, that we are not justified in accepting blindfold the formulation of principles which guided Einstein to his formulae.

You will have observed that for reasons which I have briefly indicated, I maintain the old-fashioned belief in the fundamental character of simultaneity. But I adapt it to the novel outlook by the qualification that the meaning of simultaneity may be different in different individual experiences. Furthermore, since I start from the principle that what is apparent in individual ex perience is a fact of nature, it follows that there are in nature alternative systems of stratification involving different meanings for time and different meanings for space. Accordingly two events which may be simul taneous in one instantaneous space for one mode of strati fication may not be simultaneous in an alternative mode.

Time and Space. The homogeneity of time with space arises from their common share in the more fundamental quality of extension which is a quality belonging exclu sively to events. By extension I mean that quality in virtue of which one event may be part of another or two events may have a common part. Nature is a continuum of events so that any two events are both parts of some larger event.

5—2

68 SOME PRINCIPLES OF PHYSICAL SCIENCE [CH

The heterogeneity of time from space arises from the difference in the character of passage in time from that of passage in space. Passage is the same as significance, and by significance I mean that quality of an event which arises from its spatio-temporal relationships to other events.

For the sake of simplicity I will speak of events whose dimensions are ideally restricted. I will call them * event-particles.' Also we may conceive of an event restricted except in one dimension. Such an event may be termed a route or path, where I am now thinking of a route of transition through the continuum of nature. A route may evidently be also conceived as a linear chain of event -particles. But its essential unity is thereby lost. A 'spatial' route is a route which lies entirely in one instantaneous space. A ' historical ' route is such that no two of its event -particles are simultaneous according to any time-system. Along such a route there is a definite antecedence and subsequence in time which is independent of alternative time-systems.

Thus the distinction of time from space, which I have just asserted, consists in the fact that passage along a spatial route has a different character from passage along a historical route. For proof of this fact think of a spatial route which has a material particle situated in each of its event-particles. We pronounce at once that all these material particles are different, because no material particle can be in two places at the same time. But if a historical route is in like case and the material particles be of like character even with some differences, we equally pronounce them to be the same material particle at successive stages of its existence. This difference of judgment can only arise from the distinction in the characters of spatial and temporal passage.

iv] SOME PRINCIPLES OF PHYSICAL SCIENCE 69

It only strengthens this argument when we remember that the events are the ultimate substance of nature and that the apparent material particle is an adjective of appearance which qualifies them. For the unique type of individuality possessed by the emergence of the same adjective throughout the historical route must be due to the special peculiarity of the route. I will recur to this question later when I define adjectival particles.

Time-Systems. According to the view which I am urging on you a moment of time is to be identified with an instantaneous spread of the apparent world. The relations of interconnection within this moment form a momentary three-dimensional space. Such a space is an abstraction from the full-bloodedness of a moment of time which includes all that is apparent in that space. A time-system is a sequence of non-intersecting moments including all nature forwards and backwards. I call the moments of such a consistent system * parallel/ because all parallelism is derived from their mutual relations and from their intersections with the parallel moments of other time-systems.

I am also assuming on rather slight evidence that moments of different time-systems always intersect. This hypothesis is the simplest and I know of no pheno mena that would be explained by its denial. The result is to introduce the peculiar properties of Euclidean parallelism.

One advantage of the admission of alternative time- systems is that they afford explanations of the notion of position and of the notion of evenly lying loci, such as planes and straight lines. However, I will not in this lecture enter into a detailed examination of the origins of geometry.

70 SOME PRINCIPLES OF PHYSICAL SCIENCE [CH

Permanent Space. The momentary spaces of a time- system are matters of direct observation, at least when we construe momentary in an approximate sense. They must be discriminated from the permanent space of that time- system.

Best and motion are ultimate data of observation, and permanent space is the way of expressing the connec tions of these data. The ultimate elements of perman ent space are therefore somewhat elaborate. It will be sufficient for my immediate purpose in this lecture to exhibit the meaning to be ascribed to a point of the permanent space of a time-system.

Consider observations wedded to a single .temporal mode of stratification. Some apparent bodies will be observed to be in motion and others at rest. The his torical route forming the successive situations of an apparent particle at rest for such an observer is a point in the permanent space which corresponds to that time- system. For an observer who is wedded to another time-system the same apparent particle will be moving with uniform velocity. Accordingly the point of the space of the former time-system cannot be a point of the space of the latter time-system, since to be at rest occupying one point in the space of one time-system is to be moving through a succession of points in the space of another time-system. A permanent point is thus highly complex and only serves for one particular specification of the meaning of space and time. Each event-particle will occur at one point in each permanent space, and is thus the vertex of a pencil of points, one point for each time-system.

Each point intersects any moment, of whatever time- system, in just one event-particle. There is thus a

iv] SOME PRINCIPLES OF PHYSICAL SCIENCE 71

point- wise correlation between the event-particles of any momentary space and the points of the permanent space of any time-system. This correlation explains the na turalness with which observation of momentary spaces is expressed in terms of permanent space so as to gain the facile representation of the phenomena of rest and motion, which can have no existence for a single momen tary space.

This general theory of the grounds in nature for geometry and time is consistent with a rigid relativity whereby space and time are simply expressions for a certain observed ordering of events. Also it is essential to note that the spatial relations between apparent bodies only arise mediately through their implication in events. It is essential to adopt this view if we are to admit any assimilation of space and time.

The Physical Field. We now pass to the considera tion of the status of the physical field of natural science. The scope of the contingency of appearance is limited, and the conditions of limitation are what we term the laws of nature.

They are expressed by assuming that the apparent adjectives of the past indicate a certain distribution of character throughout events extending from the past into the future. It is further assumed that this hypo thetical distribution of character in its turn expresses the possibilities of adjectives of appearance attachable to the future events. Thus the regulation of future ad jectives of appearance by past adjectives of appearance is expressed by this intermediate distribution of cha racter, indicated by the past and indicating the future.

I call this intermediate distribution of character the 'physical field.' The true expression of the physical

72 SOME PRINCIPLES OF PHYSICAL SCIENCE [OH

field is always to some extent a matter of conjecture. The only guarantee for correctness is the pragmatic test that the theory works.

The physical field is not the cause of perception nor is it the object perceived. The search for a cause of perception raises a problem which is probably meaning less and certainly insoluble. The physical field is merely that character of nature which expresses the relatedness between the apparent adjectives of the past and the apparent adjectives of the future. It therefore shares in the contingency of appearance, and accordingly can not affect spatio-temporal relations.

Atomicity. Luckily the physical field is atomic, so far as concerns our approximate measurements. By this I mean that we can discriminate in the four-dimensional continuum certain regions or events, such that each exhibits a physical character which is entirely indepen dent of the physical characters of other events or of the other physical characters of that event. This physical character requires the whole region for its complete exposition. Thus atomicity implies two properties, one is the breakdown of relativity in that the atomic character is independent of the physical characters per vading the rest of nature, and the other is that we cannot completely exhibit this character without the whole corresponding region.

This physical atomic character is the only case in which the Aristotelian idea of an attribute of a sub stance holds without grave qualification, at least so far as the realm of nature is concerned. Furthermore, atomicity is a property which is capable of more or less complete realisation. Failure to attain complete atomicity is illustrated when one aspect of the physical

iv] SOME PRINCIPLES OF PHYSICAL SCIENCE 73

field modifies another aspect of it, for example, when the physical field of mass modifies that of electro- magnetism.

Observe that the practical atomicity of the physical and apparent characters is essential for the intelligibility of the apparent world to a finite mind with only partial perception. Without atomicity we could not isolate our problems; every statement would require a detailed expression of all the facts of nature. It has always been a reproach to those philosophers who emphasize the systematic relatedness of reality that they make truth impossible for us by requiring a knowledge of all as a condition for a knowledge of any. In the account of nature which I have just given you this objection is met in two ways: In so far as nature is systematically related, it is a system of uniform relatedness; and in the second place, intelligibility is preserved amid the contingency of appearance by the breakdown of related- ness which is involved in atomicity.

This breakdown of relatedness in the expression of the laws of nature is reflected into observation by our perception of material objects. Such an object is more than its colour, is more than its touch, and is more than our feeling of its resistance to push. The object, taken throughout its history, is a permanent factor conditioning adjectives of appearance, and it is a factor which is largely independent of its relatedness to other contingent facts. It is the endeavour to make precise this aspect of a perceived material object which has led to the atomicity of modern science.

Thus it is not true to say, without qualification, that the physical field is not perceived. We do recognise permanences in the relatedness of things sensed, per-

74 SOME PKINCIPLES OF PHYSICAL SCIENCE [CH

manences which are largely disconnected. The physical field is the endeavour to express precisely these per ceived permanences as atomic characters of events.

Adjectival Particles. The discussion of these recog nised permanences is reduced to an ideal simplicity by the introduction of adjectival particles, by which I mean the ideally small perceived bodies and the elementary physical particles.

I have already stated that an adjectival particle receives its enduring individuality from the individuality of its historical route. Let me now give a more precise statement of my meaning : An 'adjectival particle' is the adjective attached to the separate event-particles of a historical route by virtue of the fact that some one and the same adjective attaches to every stretch of the route. It is the outcome of the transference to the individual event-particles of a common property of all the stretches.

Accordingly the unique individuality of the particle is nothing else than the fusion of the continued sameness of the adjective with the concrete individuality of the historical route. We must not think of an adjectival particle as moving through its route. We will say that it ' pervades' its route, and that it is 'situated' at each event -particle of the route, and that it 'moves' in an orbit in each permanent space.

It follows from this conception of the meaning of an adjectival particle that the expression of its properties should require the consideration of stretches of its route. In order, even now, to attain ideal simplicity we proceed to the limit of making all such stretches infinitesimally small. A stretch of a historical route, as thus employed in the process of proceeding to a limit, will be called a 'kinematic element.' A kinematic element is equivalent

iv] SOME PRINCIPLES OF PHYSICAL SCIENCE 75

to both the position and the velocity of an adjectival particle in any permanent space at any time.

Mass -Particles. A mass-particle is an adjectival par ticle. It follows that for some limited purposes we can treat it as being situated in an event-particle, but that for the final purpose of enunciating the laws of nature we must conceive it as pervading a stretch of its his torical route.

Consider [cf. figure, p. 31] first the former conception of a mass-particle m as situated at an event-particle which we will call P. The physical field due to m at P has to stretch away into the future. It is to be a limited atomic field with a foot in two camps, for it represents the property of the future as embodied in the past. It may therefore, so far as it is completely atomic, be ex pected to consist of that region within the future from P which has peculiar affinities with the region co-present •with P.

Now what I call the kinematic future from P is the region traversed by the pencil of permanent points which has P as vertex, considering only the portions of those points which stream into the future from P. It will be remembered that there is one such point for each time-system. Again the region co-present with P is the region reached by the moments containing P. It will be remembered that each moment is an instan taneous three-dimensional space, and that there is one such moment for each time-system. Both these regions, the kinematic future from P and the region co-present with P, are four-dimensional. The ordered geometry of the four-dimensional continuum shows that the boundary region which separates the two is a three-dimensional region which belongs to neither. This three-dimensional

76 SOME PRINCIPLES OF PHYSICAL SCIENCE [CH

region will be called the 'causal future' from P. It has all the properties that we want for an atomic region completely defined by P and for its delimitation not dependent upon any contingent characters of the rest of nature.

The atomic physical field of the mass-particle at P is P's causal future together with P itself. We will call P the origin of the field. The physical character of this field as a whole is what is meant by the mass-particle at P. This is merely Faraday's conception of the tubes of force as constituting the physical particle, with the modification that the tubes in the act of streaming through space also stream through time. Conceived under the guise of time and permanent space the mass- particle is a transmission of physical character along its lines of force with a definite finite velocity.

Metrical Formulae. A few mathematical formulae are now necessary for my argument. The assumption, adopted as the simplest representation of observed facts, that the permanent space of each time-system is Euclidean, leads to the formulae of the special theory of relativity. There is however this difference that the critical velocity c has no reference to light, and merely expresses the fact that a lapse of time and a stretch of spatial route can be congruent to each other.

Define the quantities

OV, |> = 1,2, 3, 4J|

by <=1, |> = 1, 2, 3] | (1).

o>/= -c2

Let a rectangular Cartesian system of coordinates in the permanent space of the 'x' time-system be (xlt x2) xs) and let the lapse of x-time since zero time be x4 . Thus (xlt x2, xs, x4) are the four coordinates of an event-

iv] SOME PRINCIPLES OF PHYSICAL SCIENCE 77

particle, which we will name X. Also in the ly' time- system, we denote analogously a permanent point by the Cartesian coordinates (ylt y3, ya) and a lapse of y-time by y,. Let (y,9 y^y^ y,} and (xl9 xz, x3, x4) denote the same event-particle.

Then [cf. The Principles of Natural Knowledge, Ch. xin] the relations between the two systems of coordi nates, the *x' system and the 'y' system, are of the form ^(^-^) = 2^awaxa, |> = 1, 2, 3, 4]... (2),

a

where the symbol S means summation for a = 1, 2, 3, 4 successively, and the I's are constants satisfying the conditions 2^ = 0, 0*j8]l

-1, [a-fflj

These conditions entail analogous formulae for the con verse transformation from '?/' to '#.'

It follows that, if the coordinates of another event- particle, named P, be (plt pz, p3, p4) in the 'x' system and (qlt q,, q3, q,) in the y system,

Let r(X) and r^ be respectively the x-distance and the ^/-distance between X and P. Then this invariant for X and P can be expressed indifferently either by

IA\ or by ' '

Then

(i) X and P are co-present, if

cPfa-jpjr-ffr^O,

(ii) P is kinematically antecedent to JT, if

X4>j94, and C2(x4-p4)2-r(:r)2>0, (iii) X lies in the causal future from P, if

78 SOME PRINCIPLES OF PHYSICAL SCIENCE [CH

Routes of Adjectival Particles. Let the mass-particle M be situated at X and the mass-particle m be situated at P, and let X' and Pf be event-particles respectively neighbouring to X and P on the historical routes of M and m in the four-dimensional continuum of nature. Let their coordinates be respectively

(x^ + dx^ ...) and (p^ + dp^ ...), [ju = l, 2, 3, 4]. These are accordingly infinitesimal invariants dGM~ and dGn?, respectively expressing a spatio-temporal property of the kinematic elements XX' and PPr. This property depends on the existence of the whole bundle of diverse time-systems without special emphasis on any one of them. These invariants [cf. equation (4)] are expressed by

Let the route of M be expressed by assuming xlt xz, x3 to be appropriate functions of o?4J and the route of m by assuming plt p«, ps to be appropriate functions of p^. Thus, always in reference to these assumptions, we write

Also we put and

vm*

and

Impetus. In order to exhibit the character of the physical field due to a mass-particle we must consider

iv] SOME PRINCIPLES OF PHYSICAL SCIENCE 79

it as pervading a kinematic element, which has the advantage over an event-particle of retaining the quality of historic passage. A loss of spatial dimensions is com paratively immaterial, though it probably represents a simplification beyond anything which obtains in nature.

In expressing the physical field due to ra we must therefore consider the kinematic element PPr of its route. Also we must take any arbitrary element XX', and consider how its qualifications as a possible kine matic element of the route of Mare affected by the fact that m pervades the element PP'.

Each kinematic element, such as XX', having X as initial starting-point will have certain physical charac ters. The assemblage of quantities defining these physical characters for this pencil of elements constitutes the physical field at X. The two such characters which we need consider, as qualifying XX' for pervasion by M, are its potential mass impetus and its potential electromagnetic impetus.

The potential mass impetus along XX' will be written JdJ2, and the potential electromagnetic impetus will be written dF. If the mass of the particle M be also denoted by M, and its electric charge, in electrostatic units, by E, then the realised mass impetus due to pervasion of XX' by M will be

and the realised electromagnetic impetus, due to the same pervasion, will be

c~lEdF.

The total impetus along XX' realised by its pervasion by M is

(9).

80 SOME PKINCIPLES OF PHYSICAL SCIENCE [CH

Summing along the route of M between the assigned event-particles A to B, we obtain the realised impetus along this route which is symbolised by

A

If this total impetus is to be finite, it is evident that JdJ* and dF must be homogeneous functions of duiy duz, du3, du± of the first degree, where (u19 u^ u3, u4) are any generalised coordinates of X. Thus, guided empirically by the ascertained character of dynamical equations and of the electromagnetic field, we can assume

Thus \\jy\\ is a symmetric covariant tensor of the second order and ||jF*J?|| is a covariant tensor of the first order. The elements of these tensors are functions of the co ordinates of X, that is, of (u19 u2,u3) u4). These tensors define the physical field at X so far as inertial and electro magnetic properties are concerned. Hence, writing as above

for differentiation along the route of M, -=— is a function

of u1} u.2, u3, and of u19 u2, u3, u4. We now assume that the actual route of M satisfies the condition that the realised impetus is stationary between A and B for small variations of route. We thus obtain the equations of motion

0, [M =1,2, a] ...(ii).

iv] SOME PRINCIPLES OF PHYSICAL SCIENCE 81

Expression for the Gravitational Field. I will now confine myself to the proper determination of dJ2, as affected by the existence of other mass-particles m, m', etc., in other routes. In expressing the conditions re straining the contingency of appearance it is necessary that we have recourse to that aspect of nature which is independent of this contingency. The only such aspect is that arising from spatio-temporal properties. Also dGM2 and dG^ are the invariants expressing the quan titative aspect of the historical passage of the elements XX' and PP'.

Again in considering the physical character of XX' as affected by m in its route, we must select that kinematic element PPf of m's route which is causally correlated with XX'. By this I mean that PPf has a point-wise correlation with XX' such that X is in the causal future from P and X' is in the causal future from P '. With this correlation the physical character of PP' is already determined when XX' occurs.

This assumption of causal correlation is mathematically expressed by the relation

x,-p, = r(x]jc .................. (12)

between corresponding event-particles on XX' and PP' .

The main empirical facts of gravitation are expressed by the assumption that

......... (13),

where 2 means the summation for all mass-particles

m

such as m in kinematic elements such as PP1 ', causally correlated to XX', and ^m expresses the gravitational law of fading intensity. The factor 2/c2 is inserted so that, when the main intensity is empirically adjusted w. R. 6

82 SOME PRINCIPLES OF PHYSICAL SCIENCE [CH

to give the main inverse square law of gravitation, Vm may be the analogue of the familiar gravitational poten tial at X due to m. It is easy to prove [cf. Part III] that, apart from any assumption of causal correlation between J^andP,

^mM^4-p4)-£n}

has an invariant value for all sets of rectangular Car tesian coordinates in all time-systems. Also with the causal correlation between PPr and XX' which we are assuming, this invariant expression reduces to

&m{r(x]-£m}'

Accordingly, guided by our knowledge of the Newtonian law of gravitation, we assume

v - _ r^ _ (14:)

"Q. {«•«-«"

where y is the familiar constant of gravitation so as to produce the scale of intensity of the main inverse square Newtonian term. If we write

then in an empty region M* satisfies

We might, if we had preferred to do so, have started from the differential equation as the only invariant form of linear differential equation of the second order, and then deduced the above solution for ^m as the only in variant solution for a single point-wise discontinuity. The procedure of thought which I have adopted seems to me to be better suited to throw into relief the funda mental ideas concerning nature.

iv] SOME PRINCIPLES OF PHYSICAL SCIENCE 83 Comparison with Einstein s Law. In the formula

corresponds to Einstein's proper timers. By identi fying the potential mass impetus of a kinematic element with a spatio-temporal measurement Einstein, in my opinion, leaves the whole antecedent theory of measure ment in confusion, when it is confronted with the actual conditions of our perceptual knowledge. The potential impetus shares in the contingency of appearance. It therefore follows that measurement on his theory lacks systematic uniformity and requires a knowledge of the actual contingent physical field before it is possible. For example, we could not say how far the image of a luminous object lies behind a looking-glass without knowing what is actually behind that looking-glass.

The above formula, assumed for dJ2, also differs from Einstein's. In his procedure the e/'s are conditioned by making them satisfy the contracted Reimann-Christoffel tensor equations. He obtains a solution of these equa tions for a single point-singularity under the assumption that the gravitational field is permanent for the coordi nates adopted so that no elements of the array ||«/^|| are functions of the time in the system of coordinates adopted. This limitation rules out any application of this solution to cases like that of the moon's motion, where the sun and earth evidently cannot both produce gravita tional fields permanent for the same system of coordi nates. My formula, given above, applies generally to all such cases. It is a matter for investigation whether the small terms depending on the motions thereby introduced into the gravitational formulae produce effects which

6—2

84 SOME PKINCIPLES OF PHYSICAL SCIENCE [CH

are verified in observation as recorded in the discrepancies of the moon's tables. I have traced some theoretical effects of these terms of the order of magnitude of one or two seconds of arc with periods of the order of a month or a year, but I have not yet succeeded in hitting on a term of a period long enough to aggregate an ob servable effect, having regard to the state of the moon's tables. We want periods of about 250 years.

If the above formula gives results which are discre pant with observation, it would be quite possible with my general theory of nature to adopt Einstein's formula, based upon his differential equations, for the determina tion of the gravitational field. They have however, as initial assumptions, the disadvantage of being difficult to solve and not linear. But it is purely a matter for experiment to decide which formula gives the small corrections which are observed in nature. So far as matters stand at present both formulae give the motion of Mercury's perihelion, my formula gives a possible shift of the spectral lines dependent upon the structure of the molecule and on the interplay of the gravitational and electromagnetic fields, and lastly, assuming a well-known modification of Maxwell's equations giving such an interplay, the famous eclipse results follow^.

Alternative Laws of Gravitation. Perhaps neither of the above formulae will survive further tests of other delicate observations. In this event we are not at the end of our resources. There are, in addition to Einstein's, yet two other sets of tensor differential equations which on the theory of nature explained in this lecture satisfy all the general requirements. These requirements are, (i) to have no arbitrary reference to any one particular

* In Part II the 'Limb Effect' and the doubling or trebling of the spectral lines are also deduced.

iv] SOME PRINCIPLES OF PHYSICAL SCIENCE 85

time-system, and (ii) to give the Newtonian term of the inverse square law, and (iii) to yield the small correc tions which explain various residual results which cannot be deduced as effects of the main Newtonian law.

The possibility of other such laws, expressed in sets of differential equations other than Einstein's, arises from the fact that on my theory there is a relevant fact of nature which is absent on Einstein's theory. This fact is the whole bundle of alternative time strati fications arising from the uniform significance of events. It is expressed, without emphasis on any one such time-system, by the Galilean tensor |(?jj?||. This tensor is defined by the property that, when expressed in terms of rectangular Cartesian coordinates (#„ x.2J x3, x4) for any time-system ' x,'

, .

Thus we have on hand two tensors, the above Galilean tensor and the tensor of the gravitational field which is

ira-

In order to formulate the differential equations in volving the gravitational laws we shall require the three-index symbols of the first and second types for both the tensors || J"MJ and 1 6rMJ. They will be written"3"

for the symbols of the first type, and

J>*, X}<«> and G{^\}(u)

for the symbols of the second type. Also the associate contravariant tensors are written || J&H and || 6rg5||, and the determinant \J($ is symbolised by J(u\

* Cf. Part II, Chapter v, equation (8), and Chapter vi, equa tion (13).

86 SOME PKINCIPLES OF PHYSICAL SCIENCE [CH

(i) Einstein's Law is

(19).

The two other laws which involve differential equations depend upon making the proper substitutions for the mixed tensor M Tr\ \\

in the following tensor equations

^^log{- <?<*>}*] -22[J5T

= o,

- ...(20).

(ii) In this law the mixed tensor equation is to stand for

(iii) In this law the mixed tensor tion above is to stand for

of the above

of the equa

- 22

G

where || T*$) \\ is some contravariant tensor arising from some quality of the electromagnetic field. This law is suited to express the interaction (if any) of the electromagnetic field on the gravitational field.

If the equations of laws (ii) and (iii) be referred to rectangular Cartesian coordinates, they become

(ii) 2^2 and

= 0, [,u,v=l,2,3,4] (21),

(Hi) ??;wT

= 0, [>, *- 1, 2, 3, 4] (22).

iv] SOME PRINCIPLES OF PHYSICAL SCIENCE 87

(iv) The fourth law has already been considered. It can be expressed in the integral form

-.(23),

where the kinematic element corresponding to dGm* is causally correlated to that corresponding to dGMz.

According to this law the fundamental character of inertial properties is derived from their intimate con nection with the abstract measure of uniform process in the spatio-temporal field. Thus JdG^ and JdGm2 are these abstract measures of spatio-temporal process in the elements XX' and PPf of the tracks of M and m respectively. The inertial physical field modifies this abstract measure of process into the more concrete potential impetus Jd>P, and full concreteness, so far as it is ascribable to nature, is obtained in the realised impetus M JdJ\

Rotation. In conclusion I will for one moment draw your attention to rotation. The effects of rotation are among the most widespread phenomena of the apparent won exemplified in the most gigantic nebulae and in the Hiinutest molecules. The most obvious fact about rotational effects are their apparent disconnections from outlying phenomena. Rotation is the stronghold of those who believe that in some sense there is an abso lute space to provide a framework of dynamical axes. Newton cited it in support of this doctrine. The Ein stein theory in explaining gravitation has made rotation an entire mystery. Is the earth's relation to the stars the reason why it bulges at the equator ? Are we to understand that if there were a larger proportion of run-away stars, the earth's polar and equatorial axes

88 SOME PRINCIPLES OF PHYSICAL SCIENCE [CHIV

would be equal, and that the nebulae would lose their spiral form, and that the influence of the earth's rotation on meteorology would cease ? Is it the influence of the stars which prevents the earth from falling into the sun ? The theory of space and time given in this lecture, with its fundamental insistence on the bundle of time-systems with their permanent spaces, provides the necessary dynamical axes and thus accounts for these fundamental phenomena. I hold this fact to be a strong argument in its favour, based entirely on the direct results of experience.

Conclusion. The course of my argument has led me generally to couple my allusions to Einstein with some criticism. But that does not in any way repre sent my attitude towards him. My whole course of thought presupposes the magnificent stroke of genius by which Einstein and Minkowski assimilated time and space. It also presupposes the general method of seek ing tensor or invariant relations as general expressions for the laws of the physical field, a method due to Einstein. But the worst homage we can pay to genius is to accept uncritically formulations of truths which we owe to it.

PART II

PHYSICAL APPLICATIONS

CHAPTER V

THE EQUATIONS OF MOTION

THE equations of motion of a mass-particle (M) are [cf. Chapter iv, equation (11)]

^L^_JL^=0, o-i,2,3]...(i),

where [cf. Chapter iv, equation (9)]

dl= MJdJ* + c~l EdF (2).

We write

dJ* = dGM* 2 2g($ du^du, (3),

^ dup du^ ' Then the equations of motion can be written

M *-(-i<?r

/5\

&p> [ft = 1,2, 3]. ..(6), p

where (uiy uZ9 us, u^) are any generalised coordinates of the situation of M.

If (xlt xz, x3, x4) are Cartesian coordinates for the spatio-temporal system '#,' these equations become

d Mx^ _^_^p,^^^^rnn. ^(x)

xf, 0=1,2,3] (7),

where

92 THE EQUATIONS OF MOTION [CHV

and F is written for T(x] . We write 2' for summation

p

for p = 1, 2, 3, excluding p = 4. Then the terms

are called the 'pure centrifugal gravitational' terms, the terms

are called the 'composite centrifugal gravitational' terms, and the term

is the 'pure gravitational' term. Also

is the electric force [electrostatic units] and

(rF(x} rF(x} ^F(x}) \cr 23 , cr 31 , CJT 12 /

is the magnetic force.

It is convenient to note for future reference that [cf. Chapter iv, equations (5) and (7)]

x , .

m = c*cim-*dP;r

Also if c(xt-p<) = r(x)t

fir then dp, = dx,-^ ............... (10).

CHAPTER VI

ON THE FORMULA FOR dJ2

WE adopt the formula [cf. Chapter iv, equation (17)]

where c (x4 p4) = r .................. (2),

and m is a typical member of the attracting particles, situated at (plt p«, p.3, p4), and r stands for r(x) in Chapter iv.

Then [cf. equations (3), (9) and (10) of Chapter v]

tta(x)dx dx - 2 2 ym dG 2 M,,, ctx ajuv z, 7~u ***

2ym

Thus

, dr\ 4"

...(3).

dr dr

2ym dr /dr . r

-'su-« O*4]

...(4).

Also

' L/^* J

>4 1 dr r Sr

> C 9^M

...(5).

94 ON THE FORMULA FOR dJ* [OH

Also

The Potentials. It is convenient to express the com ponents of || J^v |t in terms of various potential functions which have either a tensor or an invariant character for transformations between space-time systems. We will limit our statements to rectangular Cartesian coordinates.

(i) The General Potential. This is symbolised by 3>, where

Vp^ ...(7).

o m t*-

Here, as elsewhere, it is to be noticed that (xlt x2, x3, #4) lies in the causal future of (plt p^ p3, p4) where m is situated ; so that

c(x,-p.) = r.

This condition always holds unless a special exception is made.

<l> is invariant. For

is invariant. Also, dropping for the moment the causal relation between

(a^, a?8f a?,, x,) and (plt pt, p», p<), £lm{c(Xt-pt)-£} and nw-

vi] ON THE FORMULA FOR dJ* 95

are invariant. Hence

is invariant. Hence, replacing the causal relation after differentiation, we immediately find that

OJ 2' (*„ -pjp, - \ <V (r - f ) 2'lVP,

is invariant. The in variance of 3> immediately follows. (ii) The Tensor Potential. This is a covariant tensor of the first order, symbolised by

where ^= _2 ............... (8).

m d* (r £ )

The tensor property follows from the fact that

«.(*•-£)

is invariant, and that

II A. V^ II

is a covariant tensor. We note that =

(iii) The First Associate Potential. This is symbolised by A, where

A-S^^r-S) ............ (10).

Ttl C

It is obvious that A is invariant.

(iv) The Second Associate Potential. This is sym bolised by B, where

......... (11).

It is obvious that B is invariant.

96 ON THE FORMULA FOR dJ* ICH

Then, neglecting terms involving c~3 as a factor,

= (c2 + 6<S>) dx? - (l+ -2 ¥, ] ^Jdx* - 82 ^p dxpdx,

...(12).

It is now easy to transform to any other pure spatial coordinates in the ' x '-space by noting that

is a vector in the os-space, and that

2 z— dx0 = dB.

P dxp

and that, in any coordinate system (u19 uZ9 u2

is a covariant tensor of the second order, whatever may be the coordinates (ult ua) u.3, u±). Here^ (r{^, p}(u) is the ChristofFel three-index symbol defined by

0fcu%p}«-Sflfo0[/u%a]W (13).

Furthermore, to our order of approximation [i.e. neg lecting terms involving c~3], the terms involving B will disappear from the equations of motion. Accordingly from this source no terms arise in these equations which involve c"1. We shall also show that no terms of this order of magnitude arise from <I>, since these terms disappear from the approximate expression for <£.

The Contemporary Positions. It is often more con venient to express the formulae in terms of the positions of the attracting particles in the x-space contemporary with the event-particle (x19 x2, x39 x4). Let this con temporary position of the particle m be (q19 q2, q3, x4).

* The definition of «7gJ and of Gfi^ is given in Chapter x, equation (3), below, and that of G[pv, p](u} in Chapter v, equation (8), above.

vi] ON THE FORMULA FOR dJ* 97

We have to assume that r/c is a small time. Then

Let R be the x-distance between (a;,, a;2, a;,) and (qlt q,, q3), and

1-'

.(15).

Then [cf. equation (14)]

. -.(16).

We write

for suiBficient approximations to the various potential functions, neglecting terms involving c~3. Then

'

.-(18),

m C W. R.

.(19).

7

98 ON THE FOKMULA FOR dJ* [CH

We note that V(x)M° = -2 2 ............... (20),

C "

s2 s2 v •+

It easily follows [cf. equation (20)] that, if the attract ing matter be a uniform sphere in the x-space of mass M' and of radius a, then at a distance R0 from the centre of the sphere and for points outside the sphere [i.e. R^a]

(21),

(22),

(23):

and for points inside the sphere [i.e. R < a]

Associated Space. We now introduce new co ordinates (Xlf Xz, Xs, X4) which are not in general pure spatio-temporal coordinates (unless the attracting Jbodies be at rest in the os-space), but are closely associated with the Cartesian coordinates (xltxz,xz, x4). We write

1 ;) Jo

We can then by an easy transformation deduce

dJ" = (c2 + 64>°) dX; -

&

j -(27).

t + 42 - dXfdXt

VI]

ON THE FORMULA FOR dJ*

It is to be noticed that (Xlt Xz, X3, JQare transformed to (Y19 Y2, Y3, F4) cogrediently with the transformation of (xlf x2, x3, #4) to (ylt 2/2, t/3, y4). Hence we can conceive that (Xlt X^ X3, X4) and (Ylt F2, F3, F4) are two sets of rectangular coordinates to an event-particle in an 'Associated Space-Time Continuum.'

Then corresponding to a path in the #-space tra versed with velocity (xlt x.2, x3), there is a path in the associate space traversed with velocity (Xlt X,, X^), where

Y -^

~~

= 1,2, 3, 4].

Also we write

and

Now put

,(28).

A= 1 +

2 ym <?. R

(29).

The equations of motion [cf. equation (6), Chapter v, and equation (27) of this chapter] now become [for /*=!, 2, 3]

1 + JT

° - 3*°)

where

= _

...(30),

.(31),

7-2

100 ON THE FORMULA FOR dJ* [CH vi

and (since || F^ || is a co variant tensor)

1 rP /4°

F^^F^+^J-^F^^- (32).

« c2a>a dxpdxa

We note that throughout the small terms we can neglect the distinction between the true and the associate continua.

CHAPTER VII

PERMANENT GRAVITATIONAL FIELDS

WHEN the attracting masses (m15 m2, ...) are per manently at rest in the x-space, we obtain those par ticular cases of gravitational action for which Einstein's general equations of condition have been solved. We now have

T,=^;=O, 0=1,2,3]

X, = xt

Hence [cf. equation (27) of Chapter vi] a- = (c2-2^ 4) dX?

and [cf. equation (12) of Chapter vi] = (c2 - 2¥4) dxt* - l + ¥< S'

Thus the equations of motion become

A. dXt

....(2).

CHAPTER VIII

APPARENT MASS AND THE SPECTRAL SHIFT

IN the first place consider the vibration of some in ternal part of a molecule. Let M be its mass and V its undisturbed velocity. Then in the absence of gravitation

and in the presence of gravitation

But in either case Mt± is the effective mass. Accord ingly, assuming that the electromagnetic forces which bind together the molecule are unaltered by the presence of the gravitational field, the period of vibration is lengthened in this field from

T to

where ST/T-^v; .................. (3).

But the electromagnetic forces will be affected by the field. Accordingly, it requires some knowledge of the structure of the molecule to be certain what the shift (if any) of the spectral lines should be.

For example, assuming the electromagnetic laws con sidered under Chapters x and xui below and assuming that the cohesive forces of an atom depend on the statical distribution of electric charges, the presence of

CH vm] APPARENT MASS AND SPECTRAL SHIFT 103

the gravitational potential will (on the average) change any such cohesive force from F to

according to the formula (10*1) of Chapter xm below. Thus the shift would now become

*,V; .................. (4).

The whole question is discussed in detail in Chapters xm, xiv, and xv below.

CHAPTER IX

PLANETARY MOTION

LET the sun be the only gravitating body and let it be permanently at rest in the cc-space at the spatial origin of the coordinate-system (x19 xz, xs). The corre sponding polar coordinates are (r19 ra, r3). Then

, A = ymr^ ............ (1).

Hence *, = a>l - , [>= 1, 2, 3]... (2).

We then put

............ (3),

and evidently (JBj, r2, rs) are the polar coordinates in the associate space of the point (X19 Xz, X3).

Consider uniplanar motion of a planet in the plane

rf = 0. The equations of motion become

O-0 ..................... (5).

Thus ^R^rt = h ..................... (6).

Then transferring to r2 as independent variable and putting

«=1/^ ..................... (7),

we find

CHIX] PLANETARY MOTION 105

But, to our approximation,

y'ra'V ¥4 = yww-£— j— ............... (9).

c/

Thus the equation becomes

Now K is the constant energy of the orbit on the sup position that c is infinite. Hence, to our approximation, c~*K is constant. We now put

u = ri(l+ecos0) ............ (11),

where

6 = (l-k)rz + a ............... (12),

and immediately deduce

4 \ .

(lo)

272 A2 c2/r c2

7

and A=

This value for & is Einstein's result.

The path of the planet in the as-space is

(15).

l l

It is to be noticed that we have not assumed that e is small.

It is evident that Kepler's second law receives a slight modification, since

hb-1 .................. (16).

CHAPTER X

ELECTROMAGNETIC EQUATIONS

WE have to consider a modification of the Maxwell- Lorentz Equations which will exhibit an influence of the gravitational field on the electromagnetic field.

The electric and magnetic forces in the #-space are expressed by the skew symmetric tensor

II*U

where

Hence it follows that, if

A

then

Thus one set of four out of the Maxwell-Lorentz equations is identically satisfied. We now choose the remaining set of four in a form which exhibits a gravi tational influence. Let || </M" || denote the contravariant tensor conjugate to || J^v ||, defined by

= 1, |> = v]J '

We then define the skew contravariant tensor

!(•»)

Then since || (JF is skew,

is a contravariant tensor.

CHX] ELECTROMAGNETIC EQUATIONS 107

Also let p(x) be the electric density in the #-space, so that

is the Contra variant Electric Motion Tensor. Then the second set of the remaining four of the Maxwell-Lorentz equations is

?l-(jy)S = ^*,, 0=1,2,3,4]...(5).

If the circumstances are such that the gravitational elements [i.e. J$~\ can be taken as constant throughout the region of the electromagnetic field, then [cf. eqn. (3) above] we can write these equations in the co variant form

O J/X*) A

ratf-TA tTTy) . w^) f\ _

LA-

CHAPTER XI

GRAVITATION AND LIGHT WAVES

THE wave-lengths of light waves are short compared with the linear dimensions of any region within which the gravitational elements vary. Also it is possible to assign regions such that the gravitational elements are constant within them and yet large enough to contain areas of wave-fronts of linear dimensions large com pared to the wave-lengths. Also any lengths expressive of the curvatures of the wave-fronts may be assumed to be large compared to the linear dimensions of such regions, at least in the application considered below.

It follows that the characteristic equations for light waves in uncharged space are [cf. equation (6) of Chapter x]

In the corresponding coordinates of the associate con tinuum these equations become

Also with our assumption as to the constancy of the e/'s, X^ is a linear function of xlt x.2) x3, #4. Hence a plane wave in the x- space is a plane wave in the associate JT-space.

Now assume

K

Then our conditions give

0 ........................ (4),

CHXI] GRAVITATION AND LIGHT WAVES 109

...(5).

We derive therefore a determination of VFl + F4 as a multiple of the small quantity

and the equation

V*J£-2VJ£> + J& = 0 ............ (6)

for the determination of V.

Assume that the gravitating bodies are permanently at rest in the x-space. Then [cf. equation (ri) of Chapter vn and equation (3) of Chapter x]

(X)

Also, measuring along the normal (in JT-space) to the plane wave,

Hence the equation for V becomes

dJ* = 0 ..................... (9).

Thus Einstein's assumption is proved for the normal advance of very short electromagnetic waves, such as the light waves, considered as advancing in associate space. This result holds for any short waves for which the radii of curvature of the wave-fronts are large compared to the wave-lengths. For then a small area of wave- front can be treated as plane.

Now consider a ray from a fixed point P to a fixed point

110 GRAVITATION AND LIGHT WAVES [OH

Q in the x-space. By Huygheiis' principle its course is given by making the time T to be stationary for small variations of the path between these points. Now by comparison with the associate space, since the gravita tional field is permanent, X4 and x4 are identical. Thus

P p

But V is given by

=0 ...... (11).

Now V is nearly equal to c. Hence to our approximation

Thus

P

Thus, keeping PJandjQ fixed,

(14).

Thus the associate path of the ray in the associate space is obtained by assuming the associate space to be filled with a medium of refractive index

Also in the particular case when the gravitational field is due to the sun, the refractive index is

hc2^ '

and since A is a function of i\ only, the polar coordinates (r19 ra, r3) in the #-space correspond to the polar co ordinates (R, r2, r3) in the JT-space. Hence the angle subtended at the sun by the two points at infinity on the ray in the x-space is equal to the analogous angle

xi] GRAVITATION AND LIGHT WAVES 111

subtended at the sun by the two points at infinity on the associate ray in the JT-space. Thus Einstein's result as to the deviation immediately follows.

Furthermore, it follows from the expression for T, that no modification of interference fringes can arise, due to the terms in dJ2 involving B, by the use of an apparatus by which alternative rays for light, originating from the same source at P, are sent along alternative paths from P to Q, since

[1 CQ I O \ ~~I other path

\ }+-^\dS\ ...(15).

Cjp\ C* V Jonepath

If ^4 be constant along the paths, this equation be

comes other path 1 / 2 \ other path , .

I1 Jonepath 0\l *tf 4) L J one path '

Now on the surface of the earth, if the axes of co ordinates be fixed relatively to the surface and the axis of x3 be vertically upwards, we have [cf. equations (22) and (26) of Chapter vi]

-

*-» 5 c2 '

where g is the gravitational acceleration and a is the earth's radius.

It follows that S = s.

Accordingly, if the alternative geometrical paths of a divided ray be of equal geometrical length,

p rrrt other path _ ^ L J one path

Thus in any experiment of the Michelson-Morley type, the earth's gravitational field will produce no modifica tion of the interference fringes. The null result of the Michelson-Morley experiment is therefore fully explained.

CHAPTER XII

TEMPERATURE EFFECTS ON GRAVITATIONAL FORCES

ASSUME that the attracting body is at rest, except that its separate molecules have a velocity of agitation of which the mean square is w2. Let Av stand for 'Average value of.' Consider

AvdJ\

We use the formula of Chapter vi, equation (12), for dJ2 and the values of the potentials given in equations (7) to (1 1) of that chapter. Then R refers to the permanent position of a molecule, neglecting its agitation due to temperature.

Write

m R

and note that

Then we easily find AvdJ* = jc2 - 2 (l + £ U-\ ^1 ^;

A

...(3).

Thus the gravitational potential ¥ requires the co efficient

due to the temperature of the attracting body.

CHXII] TEMPERATURE AND GRAVITATION 113

The coefficient due to the temperature of the attracted body is complicated by the change of apparent mass due to the velocity of agitation and by the possible effect of this velocity on the electromagnetic forces. Accord ingly the special circumstances must be known before any calculation can be applied.

Returning to the consideration of the correction for the temperature of the attracting body, let 6r, and u? be its gravitational attraction at a given point and the mean square of its molecular velocities when its absolute temperature is T19 and G0 and u^ be analogous quan tities when its absolute temperature is T0. Then

< = a7;, M02 = aT0 (4),

where a is some constant depending on the physical constitution of the body. For example, for water vapour

at

<=5x 109 [cm.2/sec.2], T0 = 273° (5).

Hence a= 1'83 x 107 (approx.) (6).

Hence, putting

a = a'xl07 (8),

we find

Thus the temperature correction due to ordinary molecular velocities is inappreciable. It may be the case however that we should consider the velocities within each molecule, particularly within the nucleus of an atom. It may well be that such velocities attain to a sensible fraction of the velocity of light. The temperature correction might then be appreciable, w. B. 8

CHAPTER XIII

THE ELECTROSTATIC POTENTIAL AND SPECTRAL

SHIFT

SINCE the gravitational field is permanent [cf. equation (1-2) of Chapter vn]

= (c2 - 2^4) dx? -

•'•\ /*

We also assume (as in Chapter xi) that in the region considered the gravitational field is practically uniform, so that the spatial rate of variation of g^v is negligible. This amounts to neglecting gravitational accelerations but retaining gravitational potentials or quasi-potentials.

Wewrite

so that "^ and A^ [/x, v = 1, 2, 3] are constants through out the region considered.

Neglecting terms involving c~4 as a factor, we find

...(4), (5),

(6).

CHXIII] ELECTROSTATIC POTENTIAL 115

Hence putting X = 4 in equation (6) of Chapter x, we find that in a steady electromagnetic field and a per manent gravitational field, the equation for the electro static potential becomes

Hence the solution for a point-charge e at the origin is

(8),

where ?\ is the distance of the point (xlt x.2, x3).

Now consider a number of molecules in the region each forming an isolated electrical system. Let each molecule have an axis-system (xlt x2, a?3) at the centre of its nucleus, and let each such axis-system have the same relation to its electrical configuration as any other such axis-system has. But the molecules are orientated in every possible manner with respect to the gravitating field.

Hence if e be the charge at the centre of the nucleus which can be conceived as keeping the molecule together, and e' be the charge of any part of the molecule whose vibration is being considered, it follows that on the average the cohesive radial force is

But V2

c

} ............ (9).

Hence the average cohesive force on that element of the molecule is

8—2

116 ELECTROSTATIC POTENTIAL [CHXIII

But the apparent mass of the element due to the gravitational potential is

where M is its apparent mass in the absence of the field. Hence, if T be the period of vibration of the element in the absence of the gravitational field and T-}- Sj T in its presence,

?^-L* (11)

T -6c»^«" .-111J.

Einstein's formula for the shift of the spectral lines is

For observational purposes the two formulae are in distinguishable.

CHAPTER XIV

THE LIMB EFFECT

LET a> = aMrlf [>=1,2,3] ...... (1).

Then [cf. equation (8) of Chapter xiu]

a.} ............ (2).

Here (a1? a2, a3) are the direct ion- cosines of the vector from the origin to (xlt x2, x.A). Thus the radial force is

Now consider the internal vibration of a molecule which radiates light of period T (in a non-gravitational field) as capable of being represented as the vibration of a variable electric Hertzian doublet with this period.

Let (alf a2, a3) be the direction-cosines of the axis of the doublet. Then owing to the gravitational field the electric force which controls the vibration of the doublet is changed by the presence of the factor

M v **" M

Let T become T+8'T owing to the joint effect of this factor and of the change in the apparent mass of the electrons forming the doublet (due to the gravitational field). Then

8'T

Let there be a large number of electrons forming the atmosphere of a star (say, the sun). Let the observer

118 THE LIMB EFFECT [OH

be at a great distance along the axis of x^ Put

c&! = cos Oj, a2 = sin Oj cos a2, a, = sin a: sin a2. . . (5). Now doublets radiate light unequally in different directions. The intensity (measured by the energy radiated) varies as the square of the sine of the colatitude of the direction, the latitude being reckoned from the equatorial plane of the doublet. Thus the intensity of the light from the doublet in direction (a,, a.2, as) sent to the observer varies as sin2 ax. Also the average change of period (8T) of the light sent to the observer with colatitude a, (as reckoned from the equatorial planes of the doublets) is given by

1 p-S'T

2. 0 -T

i.e. by

S'T 1 3^

...(6).

sin2 ax cos2

Now the light from the molecules for which ax is nearly 90° will be the brightest, both because of the factor sinX in the intensity, and because the equa torial belt of angular space of breadth d^ is greater than the belts of the same angular breadth as c^ approaches zero. Hence the shift of the spectral lines will approach that given by taking ax = ?r/2. This con clusion is reinforced by the discussion of the next chapter on permanent directions of vibration at least so far as relates to the centre or the edge of the sun's disc. Thus

xiv] THE LIMB EFFECT 119

Now let en be the radius of the sun, and let the centre of the sun be the point

( a cos {}„ a cos /32, a cos /?8),

so that at the point of the sun's surface from which the light is taken the direction-cosines of the upward vertical are

(cos ft, cos&, cos/33).

Let R be the distance from the molecule at (xlt xz, x3) to the centre of the sun. Then after differentiating we can put a for R, and zero for x19xz, x3.

Then A=(&+y?) ............... (8),

where 0 <TJ <-£- ..................... (9).

It follows from equation (22) of Chapter vi that 77 would be exactly % if the sun were homogeneous. But it is probably considerably smaller.

Then ^a = = {2, + (l-3,)8in'A} ...(10). Thus = I*4 {1+^ + 1(1- 3,) sin'A} ...(11).

This formula exhibits a Limb Effect. For if the light comes from the centre of the sun, then

and = (l+i,) ............ (12);

and if the light comes from the edge of the disc, then

(13).

120 THE LIMB EFFECT [CHXIV

Hence, as we proceed from the sun's centre to its rim, there is a shift of spectral lines towards the red, defined by

Thus, if we take 77 = ^

(which is probably not far from the truth), we find &ivT 7

It is unnecessary to point out the roughness of the assumptions, particularly the conception of the molecule as a vibrating doublet emitting light. But the investi gation does suffice to show that our general assumptions do require the existence of a limb effect of the same order and sign as that actually observed.

CHAPTER XV

PERMANENT DIRECTIONS OF VIBRATION AND THE DOUBLING EFFECT

CONSIDER a vibrating element of a molecule of charge e', the charge of the central nucleus being e. Let (PU P2, P3) be the mechanical force on the element due to the electrostatic attraction of the nucleus. Then [cf. equation (8) of Chapter xm]

> ee'x* r

*~ r3 1

2ee'

= 1,2,3]

...(1).

Let this element of the molecule be that element whose radial vibration in direction (alt a.2, a3) constitutes the variable doublet to which the radiation of the light is due. This direction of vibration cannot be permanent unless the force (P15 P2, P3) is in the direction (al9 a2, a3), when

x. = W.> [5=1,2,3] (2).

Hence for permanence we require

V 4 n rr* n [~e 1 9 3~l f'l\ 2* Si^Ctp OC as, [_.S 1, <6, OJ...^O^.

/*

Consider a molecule in the atmosphere of the sun as in the previous chapters. Then [cf. equations (8) and (10) of Chapter xi v]

1

<r " 1

= ~ - ? cos cos , . -

...(4).

122 THE DOUBLING EFFECT [CH

Hence

aM = ^-~ ^4 cos fa S'aM cos fa

+ p*4as .-(5). Hence

aM cos or

Thus a permanent direction of vibration must be either normal or tangential to the gravitational level surface.

Accordingly, in the gaseous mass of molecules forming the atmosphere of the sun there will be an excess of molecules with their vibrations either normal to the level surface or in one of the directions tangential to the level surface.

First consider the vibrations normal to the level surface, and as in the previous chapter let the observer be on the axis of xl at a great distance. Then for these vibrations we should put

a, = cos&, [*=!, 2, 3] ...... (7).

Thus [cf. equation (4) of Chapter xiv]

t.

-y*. .............. •• ...................... ••••<»>•

Thus these molecules yield a constant shift of the spectral lines all over the sun's disc. But the intensity of the light due to them varies as sin2 /^ . Accordingly,

xv]

THE DOUBLING EFFECT

123

they should yield faint lines from the centre of the disc and comparatively strong lines from its edge.

Secondly, consider molecules vibrating tangentially to the sun's gravitational level surface. No generality is lost by taking the axes of x2 and x3, so that the sun's diameter through the point of the disc considered is in the plane x^. In this case

I- -(9).

Also the level surface at the point contains the axis of x3.

x*

Then we can put

«! = sin 9 sin /3X = sin 8 cos ft.2 *

az = sin 0 cos &

a3 = cos 0 Hence equation (4) of Chapter xiv becomes

...(10).

T

- \ sina 0 (Au cos2 ft - 2An cos ft cos & + A* cos2 ft) ^^33 cos2 0 sin 0 cos 0 (A^ cos ft ^431 cos ft).

124 THE DOUBLING EFFECT [OH

By the use of equations (4) of this chapter, this reduces to

T ~ 2c* 4

To consider the comparative brightness of light from these molecules taken at different points [i.e. for different values of ft] note that [cf. equations (10) of this chapter]

sin2 a, = I - a,2 = 1 - sin2 0 sin2 ft ...... (12).

Hence the total light from this type of molecule is brightest at the centre of the disc [ft = 0], since for every value of 0

sin2 ^=1 ..................... (13).

The brightness falls off as we pass towards the edge

/ 7T^

of the disc, and finally at the edge ( ft = -

2

sin2 ax = cos2 6 Also the average value for sin2 c^ at any point is

l-isin2ft (15).

It will also be noticed that the larger angular area of an equatorial belt of angular breadth 28^ over a polar cap of angular diameter 28^ gives the tangential molecules another advantage in brightness over those of the former type vibrating normally to the level surface.

To sum up the discussion on the shift of the spectral lines contained in this and the two preceding chapters : The molecules in the sun's atmosphere can be sorted into three groups, (i) a group of molecules uniformly pointing in all directions, (ii) a group of molecules pointing normally to the gravitational level, and (iii) a

xv] THE DOUBLING EFFECT 125

group of molecules pointing tangentially to the gravi tational level. A molecule is said to point in the direction of the equivalent electric doublet whose varia tion generates the light waves.

The relative brightness of the light from these three groups changes as we pass from the centre to the edge of the sun's disc. It is constant for group (i), it varies as sin2 ft for group (ii), and it varies as (l ^ sin2 ft) for group (iii).

The spectral shift for group (i) is on one hypothesis [cf. Chapter xm]

!_*

6c° 4)

and on another hypothesis [cf. equation (11) of Chap ter xiv] it approximates to

where 77 is probably not greater than ^Q. The spectral shift for group (ii) is

3 ~ 2rJ «, ~~2dr^4'

The spectral shift for group (iii) is

2_±2<p

2c2

Accordingly, in light derived from the sun, or a star, or a nebula in (1) a general shift of the spectral lines to the red may be expected ; (2) since groups (ii) and (iii) change in relative importance as we pass from the centre to the edge of the disc, and since the shift due to group (i) also changes, so a shift of spectral lines towards the red (the limb effect) may be expected ; (3) in the case of the sun or a nebula some evidence of

126 THE DOUBLING EFFECT [CH xv

a doubling or even a trebling of the spectral lines may be expected.

It is also to be noticed that the number of vibrations of a doublet emitting light from the visible spectrum during a mean free path of the molecule is of the order 104, even allowing for the fact that the velocity of the molecule is largely due to a high temperature. Accord ingly, within each mean free path there is time for the vibrations to settle down into one of their permanent directions.

Finally, we note that when it shall be possible to measure with reasonable accuracy the spectral shifts of light from the stars and the nebulae, we obtain a numerical determination for the mass divided by the radius of the body concerned. Hence if either the mass or the radius be known, the other can be found.

CHAPTER XVI

STEADY ELECTROMAGNETIC FIELDS

THE equations (6) of Chapter x for a steady electro magnetic field become

y<y, 0=1, 2, 3]...(i).

Consider a region where there is no current and let F^ |>, v= 1, 2, 3, 4] be the value of F^ which is the first approximation when the gravitational influence is neglected.

We use equations (3) to (6) of Chapter xm and put

We also take £1 as the magnetic potential for the approximate magnetic force (cFZ3°, cF3l°, cF^), so that

(cFj, cFJ, cFJ)= -gradft ......... (3).

The equations to determine the magnetic force

(cF,, cF3l, cFK) now become

curl (Si, S,, S,) = Q ............... (4),

where

an 2/dBdF° dB3F4°\ /cx Si^cFv-VSfA+z- +-U-^r-5-^r —(5),

dxv C \dx., dx2 dx.2 dx3 1 with analogous meanings for £ and >S3.

128 STEADY ELECTROMAGNETIC FIELDS [CH

Hence the second approximation gives cF, = cFJ - 2 {AucFa' + AacFJ + AacFj}

- ...(7),

- 2 { cFJ + AxcF3? + A.cFj}

_2M 35 ....

In the first place we note that a steady electric force (Fu, F^,FU) in a permanent gravitational field produces the magnetic force

where \_H.Rf~\ stands for the vector product of the two vectors R and Rf.

Accordingly, the magnetic force is perpendicular to the electric force which produces it and to the vector grad B.

Consider a field on the surface of the earth. Let a be the earth's radius and let the axis of xl be the upward vertical. Then at the origin (which is on the earth's surface)

grad£ = (^4, 0, o) (9),

where [cf. equation (23) of Chapter vi]

076 ... <e<l.

Here e would attain its lower limit if the earth were uniform throughout. We shall assume

e = 0'88 (10)

xvi] STEADY ELECTROMAGNETIC FIELDS 129

as a sufficient approximation in the actual circum stances.

Hence the magnetic force produced by the electric force

a, Fsina, 0)

is ^.(0,0, -sin a),

c/

i.e. is the horizontal force

2ega ^ . -~ Fsma, c

perpendicular to the vertical plane containing the electric force and proportional to the sine of the angle which the electric force makes with the vertical. Here g denotes the ordinary gravitational acceleration.

Accordingly, a given electric force produces the greatest magnetic effect when it is horizontal. But in any case the magnetic force produced is extremely small, being about

r2xlO~9x^sin a (gausses),

where F is the measure of the electric force in electro static units.

The corresponding effect on the surface of the sun would be about

3*8xlO~Bx^sinct (gausses).

This effect is the only effect I have found which depends on the existence of B. Accordingly, an experiment of sufficient accuracy to detect the magnetic force, if it exists, would be of great interest as forming a crucial experiment to test the formula for dJ2 here adopted.

A steady magnetic field is also modified by the presence of the gravitational field.

W.R. 9

130

STEADY ELECTROMAGNETIC FIELDS

[CH

For example, consider a current / (electromagnetic measure) along the axis of xlt and let R be the distance of (xlt x.2, x.d) from this axis. Then

,(11).

R

Let the wire (i.e. the axis of xt) make an angle ft with the upward vertical, and let the axis of x2 lie in the vertical plane through the wire. Also let the plane through the wire and the point (xlt x2, x3) make an angle with this vertical plane through the wire. Then we find [cf. equations (4) of Chapter xv]

AU = - (1 - 817) sin ft cos ft . - = Q

Hence [cf. equation (6) above]

...(12).

c~ K

Thus there is a small magnetic force parallel to the wire which is equal to

(l-3i))ga . n0 21

—-12- - cos (j> sin 2ft x -p-

G s\i

at distance R from the wire.

This force vanishes if the wire be vertical or hori zontal and is greatest when the wire is inclined at an angle of 45° to the vertical. Also it is greatest in the vertical plane through the wire, and vanishes in the plane through the wire perpendicular to this vertical plane.

xvi] STEADY ELECTROMAGNETIC FIELDS 131

Thus its greatest value at a distance R from the wire &— ^ , and cj> = 0 or TT\ is

(l-3rj)ga 2/ /

—jT ~ x R (gausses).

Hence, taking 77 = ^ , its greatest value at distance R from the wire is about

27

£ x 10 9 x - (gausses).

9—2

CHAPTER XVII

THE MOON'S MOTION

ASTRONOMICAL tables, which depend on observations made at all times of the year, must finally register spatio-temporal elements in terms of the space -time which is the rest-system of the sun. We must therefore distinguish between relative motion and difference motion in respect to a given space -time. Thus the relative motion of the moon with respect to the earth is the motion of the moon in the earth's rest-system at the moment of observation. But the difference motion of the moon from the earth in the sun's rest-space is the vector excess of the motion of the moon over that of the earth reckoned in the sun's rest-space. On the classical theory of a unique space and unique time difference motion and relative motion were identical. We have to treat them as distinct with distinct formulae. It is evident that astronomical tables for the moon concern the difference motion of the moon from the earth with respect to the sun's rest-system of space-time.

Let (xl} x2, x3, x±) be the coordinates of the moon at the time x4 with respect to rectangular coordinate axes in the sun's rest-space with the sun as origin. Let the contemporary [i.e. at the same sun-time #4] coordinates of the earth be (ql , q2, q3). We now take the earth as a moving origin in the x- space and obtain the difference coordinates for the moon, referred to moving axes parallel to the fixed axes (ylt y2, ya), where

&-*,-&, |> = l,2,3] (1);

also the difference coordinates for the sun referred to

CH xvii] THE MOON'S MOTION 133

the earth as moving origin are ( qlt <?2, <?3), where the three positions in the sun's rest-space for the sun, earth and moon are contemporary at the time xt.

The difference velocity of the moon from the earth is therefore (yl9y9,y3).

Let v be the magnitude of the velocity of the moon in the sun's rest-space, and let U be the velocity of the earth in the same space. Also let F be the magnitude of the difference velocity of the moon from the earth. Then

v*= F2 + Z72 + 22'?/M^ (2).

Also we write

s x>

Assume a uniplanar motion in the plane of the ecliptic, so that

*3 = 0, 23 = 0, 2/3 = 0 ............... (4).

Let (Rs, ra) be the polar coordinates of the earth relatively to the sun, and let (R19 R3) be the polar difference-coordinates of the moon from the earth. Thus

yl = R, cos ^3, yt = R, sin

134 THE MOON'S MOTION [CH

Also let ra be the distance of the moon from the

sun, so that

r* = R* + ^ + 2^11, cos Pa ......... (6),

where p* = R*-r* .............................. (7).

We consider R8 and r3 to be given functions of the time Xi, and take J?, and R3 as the coordinates to be determined in terms of the time by means of the equations of motion. Two propositions (A and B) are easily proved, of which particular cases are important : Prop. (A)

'

The important particular case of this proposition is

AJL^-JL^o (9)

dx.dR.r, dR,r,

Prop. (£)

jLJ^(r»r) L(r«ri) = 0 ......... (10).

The important particular case is

"'

Let (_p15 _p2, _p3, jp4) be the coordinates of the ante cedent position of the earth causally correlated to the moon's position at time x4, referred to the fixed axes origin at the sun.

Let re be the distance between the moon and this antecedent position. Also put

t* -L . i * / \ .

-i

.(12).

XVIl]

THE MOON'S MOTION

135

Then the potential impetus of the moon's route through the space-time manifold is [cf. equations (1) and (3) of Chapter vi] determined by

dJ* = (c2 - v*) dx? - 8 l - - dx-

where ms and me are the masses of the sun and earth respectively. We now put

Thus Also

Hence

+ terms due to planetary attraction (14).

(15).

(17).

c" i\

where

+ ~^TL+ cR,

...(18),

We put

wl = Rs cos p3 + Rsr3 sin 2 = Rsr3 cos p.A Rs sin

^^(R,- Rsr*) cos p3 + (Rsr3 + 2Rsr 3) sin p3 ,r3) cos yo3 - (R3 - Rsr?) sin />3 j

....(20).

136 THE MOON'S MOTION [CH xvii

Then w^w^a^, a.2 are functions of RA and x4 only. Also

(21).

Thus

TT yme r-f. & -,

±±e = -^n\^K^^^U

......... (22).

There are now [cf. equation (6) of Chapter v] two equations of motion of the type

(23).

It follows from the special cases of Props. (A) and (B), that the two terms involving c~l as a factor dis appear in both equations. Hence these equations both take the form [ft = 1, 3],

d az az d d

dx^R^ <?rl

The terms on the left-hand side of these equations are those introduced by ordinary lunar theory ; the terms on the right-hand side are the new small cor rections introduced by the formulae of relativity of the form here adopted. I have not succeeded in eliciting any terms which, in the present state of the Lunar Tables, can be made the subject of comparison with observation. The investigation will therefore not be pursued further.

PART III

ELEMENTARY THEORY OF TENSORS

CHAPTER XVIII

FUNDAMENTAL NOTIONS

1. Coordinates. The mutual relations to each other of event-particles can be determined by charac terising each event-particle by four measurements of four assigned types respectively. These four measure ments are called the coordinates of the event-particle ; and the four types of measurement must be such that (i) each type assigns to each event-particle one and only one coordinate of that type, and (ii) each set of four coordinates (as ordered in that assignment to types) characterises one and only one event-particle. Four given types of measurement with these properties are called a coordinate-system.

A coordinate-system will be called ' pure ' if one of the coordinates be the time of some given space -time system ' x ' and the other three coordinates be spatial- quantities of the space of the same system ' x" A co ordinate-system which is not pure is called ' mixed.' If (u19 u.2, u9, u4) be the coordinates of an event-particle in a pure system, then it will be adopted as a conven tion that (u19 uZ9 ua) represent the spatial coordinates of a point in the space of the space-time system to which the coordinates refer and u* represents the time in the same space-time system. Thus the event-particle (ul9 u2, u3, u4) happens at the time u4 and at the point (ul9 u2, u3) in the corresponding space.

If (u^ uz, u3, u^) and (xl9 x2, xS9 x4) be the coordi nates of the same event-particles according to different

140 FUNDAMENTAL NOTIONS [OH

coordinate-systems, the w-system and the ^-system respectively, then there will be four equations of trans formation

^=/M(»I» x-2> xs> x^ [/*=!> 2> 3, 4] ...(1).

These four equations can be solved so as to give

*> = ^K> u*> u*> *0> [>=1> 2> 3> 41 (I'l). If both systems are pure in the same space-time system, then

u, = x,,

and (ult uz, us) and (x19 xz, x3) are different spatial co ordinates of the same point in the space of that space- time system.

2. Scalar Characters and Invariant Expressions. Consider the measurement of some physical quantity arising in the physical field at an event-particle, such as the gravitational potential according to some definite meaning of that term. Its measure (so far as the defini tion of meaning is kept unchanged) must be indepen dent of coordinate-systems. But its law of distribution throughout the various event-particles of space-time will be expressible as a function of the coordinates of the event-particles under consideration.

Such a physical character is called a scalar quantity.

We must distinguish between a scalar quantity and an invariant formula expressing that quantity. When a formula in terms of coordinates of relevant event-particles is such that it gives the same value for the scalar quantity whatever coordinate-system be employed, it is called an invariant formula. There may also be formulae which are only invariant for a limited set of systems of coordinates, derivable one from the other by transformations forming a group (in

xvm] FUNDAMENTAL NOTIONS 141

the mathematical sense of that term). In this limited case we have l group invariance/

When we can conceive a scalar character in such a way that it has no special or peculiar relation of any sort to one coordinate-system of a group which it has not to any other system of that group, it follows that there must be some group-invariant formula for the scalar character which is limited to that group of systems of coordinates.

3. Physical Characters of the First Order. A scalar character is a character of zero order.

A character of event-particles is of the first order when given any coordinate -system (ult uz, u3, u^) it is expressible by an array of four quantities (functions of the coordinates of the event-particles in question) such that each quantity is specially related to one of the types of coordinate measurement. These four quantities are called the ' components ' of that character for that coordinate-system.

For example, let (ult u39 UB, u4) be a pure coordinate- system, and let a region of the it-space be filled with a continuously moving substance. Let the motion of the substance at (ult u.2, u3) at the time be represented by

Thus the array (ulf ut9 u3, 1) represents a character of the first order which is descriptive of the motion of the fluid. Again, let <X> be the gravitational potential at the event-particle (ul9 u2, u3, w4). Then the gradient

represents a character of the first order.

142 FUNDAMENTAL NOTIONS [CH

Let (x19 xz, x3, x4)be the coordinates in the coordinate- system ' x ' of the same event-particle as denoted by (uly uZ9 HS, Ut). Then (xlt x2J xa> 1) is a character of the first order descriptive of the motion by reference to the coordinate-system ' x.' We are at once brought to the consideration of the relations to each other of these two distinct descriptions of the same fact of motion by means of (ult uz, u3, 1) and (xlt x2) x3, 1) respectively.

The relations between the two will be peculiarly simple (and therefore important) if the components of one character (say the 'M-character) are expressible as linear functions of the components of the other character (the x-character), where the coefficients may be functions of the coordinates of the event-particles in question which are purely determined by the general relations of the two coordinate -systems in question and are independent of the particular values of the components. Thus if (7V10, T*(u\ T™, T4(u)) be a first order description of some fact in coordinate-system ' u,' and

be a description of the same fact in coordinate-system ' x,' the desired linear relation is

where the coefficients ZMa [//,, a = 1, 2, 3, 4] are expressible in terms of the equations of transformation between 6u' and 'x' without any reference to the particular values of

4. Tensors of the First Order. Furthermore, we pass from the two assigned coordinate-systems ' u ' and 1 x ' to the consideration of a group of systems (as in the case of invariance), if the determination of the

xvm] FUNDAMENTAL NOTIONS H3

coefficients [i.e. ZMJ can be fixed by a general rule which is identical for any two systems of the group.

A first order character as thus described in any coordinate-system of a group is called a 'Group-Tensor ' for that group.

If the general rule for the formation of coefficients in the linear relation between the components hold for all pairs of coordinate-systems whatsoever, then the character as thus described in all coordinate-systems is called a 'General Tensor' or more simply a * Tensor.' It is a tensor of the first order.

It is obvious that in the case of a group-tensor or a general tensor the rule for the formation of the coefficients in the linear equations giving the com ponents of the character for one coordinate-system in terms of the components for another coordinate-system must be such that the transformations of components from one system to another form a group. For there is to be only one description of the character in each co ordinate-system. Accordingly, if ' u,' 'v,' 'x' be three coordinate-systems and ' J" a tensor character, then the transformation of

(T™, T?\ T3(w), T™) to (T*\ T?\ T*\ I") and then of

(T™, ZV", Tf\ r4w) to (T™, T*\ T™, T^)

must give the same components in system ' x ' as the direct transformation from system ' u ' to system 'x.' In future we will write

|| 7"" ||

for the array of the components of a character in system ( u.'

144 FUNDAMENTAL NOTIONS [CH

5. Covariant and Contravariant First -Order Tensors. A tensor may refer to many event-particles. Suppose that one of these with a peculiar definite relation to the character in question is picked out and termed the dominant event-particle of the character. Let || T(u) || be the tensor in system 'u* and || T(x)\\ be the tensor in system ' x,J and let (ult u2, u3, u^) and (xl9 x2)x3, x±) be the coordinates of the dominant event- particle of the character expressed by the tensor.

The tensor is ' covariant ' if its components in any system ' u ' are related to its components in any system e x* by

n^Fff^, [/*=!, 2, 3,4]...(3).

In the case of contravariant tensors it is convenient to adopt an alternative notation (T(u)\ T(u)\ T(u)\ T(uf) for the components in any system ' u9 shortened into || T(u) || when the whole array is to be mentioned.

Then a tensor is ' contravariant ' if its components in any system * u ' are related to its components in any system ' x ' by

It is easy to prove the ' group' property of the co variant and contravariant modes of transformation by the use of the equations

. , (5-1)-

= 1, [p = V_ _

If the tensor property is restricted to a group of

xvin] FUNDAMENTAL NOTIONS 145

systems of coordinates, we obtain covariant group- tensors or contravariant group-tensors as the case may be.

6. Characters and Tensors of Higher Orders. A physical character is of the nth order when, in any coordinate system ' u,' it is expressible